The Restoration of All: Universalism in Early Christianity (part 8)

The First Origenist Controversy

    As we’ve seen in the past few posts, universalism became very popular in the church (especially the Eastern church) in the third and fourth centuries, largely thanks to the influence of Origen. However, at the end of the fourth and beginning of the fifth century, Origen’s ideas began to come under widespread attack in what came to be known as the “First Origenist Controversy.” In this post, we’ll take a look at this controversy, the role that universalism played in it, and the outcome of the controversy.

Epiphanius of Salamis

    Epiphanius was the bishop of Salamis toward the end of the fourth century, and he also founded a monastery earlier in his life (around 333). His main work was the Panarion, a heresiological writing that sought to categorize and refute eighty ‘heresies,’ including ‘Origenism.’ In his letter to John II of Jerusalem, he refers to Origen as “the father of Arius and the root and father of all other heresies” (Jerome, Letter 51.3). This charge is certainly unfair: whether or not Origen can be truly regarded as the father of ‘Arianism,’ he’s also the father of anti-‘Arianism,’ since virtually all of the prominent anti-‘Arians’ of the fourth century were influenced by him. Nonetheless, Epiphanius was staunchly opposed to Origen: in 395, he sought unsuccessfully to get Origen’s works condemned by John II of Jerusalem, and later on he assisted in the persecution of the Origenian monks of Egypt.

    Epiphanius’ detailed condemnation of ‘Origenism’ can be found in Panarion 64. He accuses Origen of teaching that the Son is of a different essence than the Father (4.5), that the souls of rational creatures preexisted their bodies (4.6–8), that Adam lost the image of God (4.9), and denying the resurrection of the dead (4.10), in support of which he quotes a lengthy excerpt from Methodius of Olympus (11.4–62.15). These mischaracterizations of Origen had already been refuted by Pamphilus at the beginning of the fourth century – he in fact held none of these views – but they were nevertheless popularized by Epiphanius. The radicalized views of Evagrius Ponticus, who did believe in a bodiless origin and restoration for rational creatures, certainly didn’t help matters. Even so, the universal restoration is conspicuously missing from Epiphanius’ condemnation, which implies that it wasn’t in dispute at the time. Later, in his 394 letter to John II of Jerusalem, he condemns the restoration of the devil, but not of other creatures.

Theophilus of Alexandria

    Theophilus was the bishop of Alexandria from 385 to 412. When the first Origenist controversy began in 395, he initially sided against Epiphanius and especially opposed his anthropomorphic view of God (Socrates, EH VI.10). At this time, Jerome accused him of harboring Origenist sympathies (Letter 63.3; 82.3). However, the church historian Socrates says that he suddenly switched his views, when the anti-‘Origenist,’ anthropomorphite monks of the desert threatened him and demanded that he condemn Origen along with his view that God is incorporeal (EH VI.7, 10). Theophilus then persecuted and exiled the Origenian monks, including the “Tall Brothers,” who fled to Constantinople where they were harbored by John Chrysostom (EH VI.7, 9; Palladius, Dialogue 7; cf. Jerome, Letter 87; 90).

    In his letter condemning ‘Origenism,’ Theophilus provides a list of accusations, including that Origen believed that Christ’s kingdom would end, our resurrection bodies will be mortal, and Christ will be sacrificed again for the demons (Jerome, Letter 92). These charges are false (in fact, Origen explicitly rejected that Christ could ever be sacrificed again in Comm in Rom V.10.12–16), and they even conflict with Epiphanius’ (also false) accusation that Origen denied the bodily resurrection. In another letter, he mentions other charges, including that Origen believed in the preexistence of souls, the eventual disappearance of bodies, and the restoration of the devil (Letter 96).

    It’s important to note that Theophilus – like Epiphanius – never condemns the universal restoration of humans, only that of the devil, which Origen did support in a sense (although he denied that this was an accurate characterization of his view; see my post on him). In any case, Theophilus’ opposition to ‘Origenism’ seems to have been more political than theological. After he managed to depose John Chrysostom, he came back into communion with the “Tall Brothers” and began to read Origen’s works once again. According to the church historian Socrates, this hypocrisy made him extremely unpopular among the people (EH VI.16–17).

Synesius of Cyrene

    Synesius was a Christian Neoplatonist philosopher, the disciple of Hypatia of Alexandria, another (non-Christian) Neoplatonist philosopher who was sadly murdered by a mob of Christians in 415, shortly after Synesius’ death. Throughout his life, he maintained a close relationship with his teacher, and even dictated a letter to her on his deathbed (Letter 16). Like Hypatia, he was interested not only in metaphysics and theology but also science, and he even corresponded to her about his need for scientific equipment (Letter 15). He was appointed by popular support to be bishop of Cyrene, Libya in 410 and confirmed in this position by Theophilus of Alexandria. Synesius composed many hymns to Christ, some of which are still used in hymnals today.

    In a letter to his brother, which he intended to be read by Theophilus before his confirmation, he said,

It is difficult, if not quite impossible, that convictions should be shaken, which have entered the soul through knowledge to the point of demonstration. Now you know that [Neoplatonist] philosophy rejects many of those convictions which are cherished by the common people. For my own part, I can never persuade myself that the soul is of more recent origin than the body. Never would I admit that the world and the parts which make it must perish. This resurrection, which is an object of common belief, is nothing for me but a sacred and mysterious allegory, and I am far from sharing the views of the vulgar crowd thereon. (Letter 105.9)

Synesius openly admits his belief in the preexistence of the soul, the eternity of the world, and a “sacred and mysterious” view of the resurrection. This is much closer to ‘Origenism’ than any of Origen’s actual views, but Theophilus evidently considered him orthodox enough to become bishop. This is further proof that Theophilus’ anti-‘Origenism’ had more to do with political opportunism than theological disagreement.

    In a letter to an accused murderer, Synesius warns that because the soul “is immortal, it bears immortal judgment,” and so if he is guilty, he should submit to punishments now lest he endure worse punishments later (Letter 44.9–10). However, he also indicates that punishment is restorative, since he says that a person who is not punished, whether by God or humans, is most unfortunate – presumably because they will remain in evil (44.13–15). Like other patristic universalists, Synesius is concerned that it may be dangerous for weaker believers to know deeper philosophical and theological truths (105.9). In his hymns, he alludes to the Neoplatonist concept of emanation-and-return of all beings, which parallels the Christian concept of creation-and-restoration (Hymn 1.9–18; 3.33–35; 6.3–5). He praises Christ for, through his incarnation, death, and resurrection, purifying all of creation including hell and saving the souls there (7.5; 9.4). Thus, Synesius of Cyrene was most likely a believer in the universal restoration.

Rufinus of Aquileia

    Tyrannius Rufinus was a monk from Aquileia in Italy, where he formed a friendship with the young Jerome of Stridon. They traveled together to Alexandria and studied under Didymus the Blind in the 370s, and Rufinus left in 380 to found a monastery in Jerusalem with Melania the Elder. There he became friends with Evagrius and John II of Jerusalem, and Jerome also moved to Bethlehem in 386 to start another monastery nearby. However, with the outbreak of the Origenist controversy in 395, Rufinus and Jerome took opposing sides: Rufinus defended Origen while Jerome became a staunch anti-‘Origenist’. Rufinus spent the next decade translating many of Origen’s works, along with Pamphilus’ apology for Origen and some of the writings of the Cappadocians and Evagrius, into Latin, until his death in 411.

    In his Apology to Anastasius, written in 400, Rufinus defends himself to the Roman pope against the charge of heresy. He defends his trinitarian orthodoxy (2), his adherence to the Nicene Creed (3), his belief in the bodily resurrection and judgment (4–5), and admits that he’s unsure of the question of the soul’s origin and its relation to the body (6). He says that, according to the Gospel, the devil and his angels (along with those who do his works) will have a portion in the aeternus fire, and that anyone who denies this will also experience the aeternus fire (5). Being proficient in Greek and a translator of Origen, he surely knew of the ambiguity of aeternus when translated from aiōnios (not aidios). Unfortunately, his Apology wasn’t enough, since Anastasius condemned both Rufinus and Origen in a letter to John II of Jerusalem the next year, although he admitted that he knew nothing of Origen before the controversy.

    Rufinus wrote an Apology Against Jerome in 401, in response to Jerome’s letter to Pammachius against ‘Origenism’ (Letter 84). In this work, he argues that Jerome himself is deeply indebted to Origen’s exegesis and followed him closely in his earlier years, so it’s hypocritical of him to now condemn Origen. With regard to the universal restoration, Rufinus quotes Jerome’s commentary on Ephesians in which he supported the eventual restoration of all rational creatures (including the being who became the devil), and cites several other patristic universalists: Clement of Rome, Clement of Alexandria, Gregory the Wonder-Worker, Gregory of Nazianzus, and their own teacher Didymus the Blind (Apol I.42–43). [1] Since Jerome accepts all of these as teachers, he’s being hypocritical to condemn Origen for holding the same belief.

    Rufinus later says that those who profess the universal restoration – including Jerome formerly – do so out of a desire to

...vindicate the justice of God... [since] it is in accordance with the good and simple and immutable nature of the Trinity to restore every creature, in the end of all things, to the state in which it was created, after long punishment over whole aeons, which God inflicts on each creature not in the spirit of anger but of correction... his design being like a physician to heal people, he will put an end to their punishment. (Apol II.12)

He continues, confessing that he’s not sure whether this doctrine is true, but it certainly “contains little impiety against God, and nothing at all of heathenism,” since its goal is to vindicate God’s justice.

Jerome of Stridon

    Jerome was an ascetic and prominent exegete from Stridon in the modern-day Balkans. Together with Rufinus, he studied under Didymus the Blind in Alexandria, as well as Apollinaris of Laodicea and other teachers. At this time, he was a close follower of Origen; in a letter from 384, he refers to Origen as “man of steel” and his opponents as “rabid dogs,” who only condemn him because they “could not tolerate the incomparable eloquence and knowledge which, when he opened his lips, made others seem dumb” (Letter 33.3–4). He also praised Origen in his work, On Illustrious Men, which he wrote in ca. 393 (De Vir 54). In the preface to his On Hebrew Names, he even said that “none but the ignorant will deny [Origen] to be the greatest teacher of the Church after the apostles.”

    In light of this, it’s unsurprising that Jerome also adopted Origen’s eschatology at that time. Within his commentary on Ephesians (1:10–12; 4:16), written in 387, he explicitly refers to the eventual restoration of sinners, the devil, and fallen angels, although he’s careful to say that they will not have the same reward (quoted in Rufinus, Apol I.31, 42). In his commentary on Nahum 2:3–7, he says that the devil (qua devil) will be punished while his “substance” will be joyfully subjected and cleansed, which was precisely Origen’s view. Throughout his early commentaries on the minor prophets, written in 390–391, he often says that God’s punishments are restorative for the sinner (e.g., Comm in Nah 1:9; Comm in Mic 1:10–15; 5:7-14; 7:8-13; Comm in Zeph 1:12; 3:9–10), and he also adopts Origen’s interpretation of John 1:3 concerning evil as a privation (Comm in Mic 2:9–10). In a 394 letter to Amandus, he interprets 1 Cor 15:24–28, saying that Christ’s body is the whole of humanity, subjection is salvific, and that God will not become all in all until every unbeliever is thus subjected (Letter 55.5).

    After his turn against Origen in ca. 395, Jerome also turned against the universal restoration, at least that of the devil. In his letters detailing his condemnation of Origen, he lists charges such as the preexistence of souls, the ‘Arian’ subordination of the Son, that Christ will be sacrificed again for the demons, the denial of the bodily resurrection, and the restoration of the devil (Letter 84.2–6; 124). He’s opposed to the idea that everyone will ultimately have the same reward (84.7), which he was also opposed to prior to his turn against Origen. Moreover, in his commentary on Jonah, written in ca. 400, he says,

I know that most [plerosque] interpret the king of Nineveh... to be the devil, who at the end of the world – since no rational creature made by God will perish – will descend from his pride and repent, and will be restored to his former place. (Comm in Nah 3:6–9 [PL 25.1141])

This shows that the concept of restoration even of the devil was still widespread at that time, but Jerome denies it on the basis that (1) it removes the fear of punishment, which Origen was also concerned about, and (2) it’s absurd to think that everyone will have the same reward in the end. He also opposes the idea that the devil could repent in Comm in Isa VI.29, written several years later.

    Jerome may still have believed in the restoration of all humanity at that point, since in the same commentary he says that Christ frees all the prisoners of Hades (Comm in Nah 2:6–7). However, by the time of the Pelagian controversy – in which Origen was once again implicated (see below) – he held that unbelievers would be punished eternally, while sinning and wicked Christians would have restorative punishment after death (Dial adv Pelag I.28). It should be noted that, although this wouldn’t be considered a form of universalism today, Augustine actually condemned this view (‘universal salvation’ of Christians) alongside the eschatological universalism of Origen (De civ Dei XXI.17–22).

Augustine of Hippo

    Augustine was the bishop of Hippo from 396 to 430, and he became one of the most influential Latin theologians of the early Western church. In his anti-Pelagian phase, he popularized the concepts of original sin and predestination. Although these doctrines existed already, they were prominent mostly in ‘gnostic’ groups in the extreme form of the so-called “doctrine of natures” (that different beings have inherently good or evil natures), and he developed a more moderate doctrine for non-‘gnostic’ Christianity. In his earlier anti-Manichaean phase, however, his beliefs were closer to those of Origen, even with regard to the ultimate restoration of creatures. [2]

    Before his conversion, Augustine was a Manichee, which was a widespread ‘gnostic’ sect that believed in a dualism of good (spiritual) and evil (material) substances along with a good and an evil deity that created them. After he became a Christian, in response to the Manichees, he adopted Origen’s arguments regarding evil being a privation. His ideas about evil at this stage are fleshed out most fully in De moribus II.1–9. His conclusion is clear: “we say that there is no natural evil, but that all natures are good and that God is the highest nature... other natures are from God and are good insofar as they are [from God]” (De Gen c Man II.43). If a being were to become completely evil, it would therefore cease to exist; but, he continues,

the goodness of God does not permit a being to be brought to this point [i.e., non-existence]. It orders all beings that fall away, so that they occupy the place most suitable to them, until by an ordered movement they return to that from which they fell away... For it has been said that nothing is allowed by the providence of God to go the length of non-existence. (De moribus II.7.9)

This was precisely Origen’s philosophical argument for the universal restoration (De Princ III.6.5). In his later Retractions (I.7.6), Augustine comments on this passage that he doesn’t believe all beings will be restored, only the beings that are to be restored will be restored (sic). Whether this means that the early Augustine was a universalist is debatable. Ramelli and Hedel argue that it does. [3] But since he never indicates in his later anti-universalist writings that he was once a universalist, I find it more likely that he was just using anti-‘gnostic’ arguments developed by earlier Christian universalists, without consciously affirming the logical conclusion of those arguments (i.e., universal restoration).

    Augustine doesn’t seem to have been particularly anti-‘Origenist’ during the first Origenist controversy. He even criticized Jerome in 405 for condemning Origen after he had previously praised him so highly (Letter 82.3.23). This changed around the time of the Pelagian controversy of the 410s. Pelagius was a theologian who argued that Christians must remain sinless to be saved, and that God’s grace is external (e.g., the giving of the Law). His views were associated by Jerome, among others, with Origen, probably due to Origen’s great emphasis on creaturely freedom of choice (Dial adv Pel III.19). This charge is certainly false, since Origen explicitly rejected the view that salvation could be achieved without grace (Comm in Rom IV.5), and Pelagius was an anti-‘Origenist’ (Augustine, De gest Pel III.10). Even so, this controversy further entrenched the opposition to ‘Origenism.’

    From around 413 onward, Augustine refuted ‘Origenism,’ including the alleged preexistence of souls and the universal restoration, in many passages (e.g., De fide et operibus XV.24; De gest Pel III.10; Ad Orosium). He frequently cites the Scriptural statements of “eternal punishment” as a slam-dunk argument against universalism, which betrays his lack of knowledge of the polysemy of aiōnios. In his City of God (XXI.17–27), he distinguishes seven views of believers whom he considers to be excessively “merciful” (misericordi): (1) that all rational beings will be restored; (2) that all humans will be restored; (3) that all humans will be saved, but only by the intercession of the saints; (4) that all who partake of the Christian sacraments, including heretics, will be saved; (5) all who partake of the Catholic sacraments will be saved; (6) all Catholic believers will be saved, some after purgative punishment; (7) all who give alms will be saved. Notably, this means that Augustine considered Jerome a misericord of the sixth type, since even in his most mature thought Jerome accepted the eventual salvation of wicked Catholics.

    In his Enchiridion (112), written in 420, he says that those believers who deny the eternity of punishment without also denying Scripture were “indeed very many” (immo quam plurimi). In fact, “very many” doesn’t quite accurately translate this phrase; plurimi is already a superlative of “many,” while quam is a further superlative meaning “as... as possible,” so this phrase should rather be translated “as many as possible” or “large majority.” This is a remarkable admission from Augustine, who by that time had become a hostile witness to universalism within the Catholic Church. [4] Because of his influence, however, the Latin-speaking church after Augustine was overwhelmingly infernalist. [5]

Paulinus of Nola

    Paulinus was a Roman poet and senator who converted to Christianity, renounced his wealth and power, and later became bishop of Nola until his death in 431. He played a peripheral role in the first Origenist controversy. Paulinus was a close friend of Rufinus, to whom two of his surviving letters (46; 47) are addressed, and he also admired Melania the Elder (Letter 29.5; Carm 21.836ff). He admired Augustine’s works against the Manichaeans, which are precisely the works in which he most strongly parallels Origen’s ideas (Letter 6.2). Jerome, even after his turn against Origen, recommended On First Principles to Paulinus to answer his question about free will (Jerome, letter 85.2–4).

    In his poems and letters, Paulinus seems to support the universal restoration of humans. In his Carmina 7–9, he anticipates the future judgment, and interprets the fire and punishment as burning and punishing people’s sins (7.30ff; 9.46ff). He does speak of eternal fires and punishment (Carm 21.506ff; Letter 1.4; 19.3; 25.3; 36.3; 40.12; 44.6), but he elaborates what he means elsewhere. The punishment will be eternal for the devil, not humanity which was deceived by the devil; the human “was punished for a short time for his improvement, but the deviser of death was doomed to eternal punishment” (Letter 23.44). At the end of his 32nd poem, when expounding God’s grace as revealed in the Son, he says,

[God] realizes that the human is a frail creature who falls easily, and though he rebukes us he will grant the same pardon to all. This is a new concept which I will declare, yet I will not repent of having said it – his fatherly love will be greater than his justice... Then in our joy we will be able to attain the kingdom of heaven, then death itself will be enabled to die, for life will be eternal and enduring. In that blessed abode there will then be no opportunity for sinning, for there is no evil desire. This is the great glory which remains in keeping for God’s faithful people...

He who conquers all is not conquered by anger itself, but judges, investigates, rebukes, spares, and glorifies. We can see from the evidence of the present that this will be... In this way we are shown that salvation will again be enacted for us in the aeon to come, and the devoted love of the eternal Father will remain forever. (Carm 32.214ff)

    Paulinus says that God’s love will outlast his justice, so that he grants the same pardon to all, and connects this to the destruction of death; salvation is not limited to this aeon, but will also be enacted in the next aeon, which we can extrapolate from God’s mercy in the present day. His focus on the faith of God’s people doesn’t negate the universalist logic of this passage, since Origen and other patristic universalists believed that all people would be saved precisely through faith. Thus, Paulinus of Nola was most likely a universalist who believed in the eventual restoration of all humans (but not the devil).

John Cassian

    John Cassian was an ascetic and theologian who helped spread Christian monasticism to the West. His thought was deeply influenced by Evagrius Ponticus and the Origenian monks of the Egyptian desert. During the first Origenist controversy, Cassian opposed the anti-‘Origenist’ anthropomorphite monks (Conferences X.2–5). He was one of the monks who fled Theophilus of Alexandria’s persecution and took refuge with John Chrysostom; after Chrysostom’s exile, he moved to the West and founded a monastery in Gaul, where he remained until his death in 435. Cassian deeply influenced later Western Christian monasticism, especially through his student Benedict of Nursia, whose “rule” is still followed by many Catholic monks and nuns. The concept of “seven deadly sins” was actually developed on the basis of Cassian’s list of “eight principal faults” (Conf V) which he drew directly from Evagrius.

    In his writings, Cassian describes the reality of terrible future punishment (e.g., Conf I.13–14; VI.3). He refers to this punishment as “eternal” (aeternus) in a few places (III.9; VI.9; XXIII.15). He depicts God’s punishment as being cleansing and remedial, even in the most severe cases, but – unlike Origen – conceives of the possibility that the Physician may be unable to cure some sinners (VI.11). Even so, he strenuously objects to the Augustinian concept of limited atonement:

For if he does not will that one of his little ones should perish, how can we imagine without grievous blasphemy that he does not generally will all men to be saved, but only some instead of all? Should some perish, they would perish against his will! (Conf XIII.7)

God’s grace is both necessary and sufficient to bring us to virtue (XIII.6). Because his will that the human being should not perish is immutable, when he sees good in us, he nurses that good since he desires all people to be saved (7). Not only does he do this, but even in those who reject him, he drags them and causes them to desire him, which Cassian repeats throughout Conf XIII.9–18. This doesn’t mean we have no free will – we have both God’s grace and free will equally (11) – but it’s a mystery how “God works all things in us, and yet all can be ascribed to free will” (18). As Ramelli correctly notes, this line of reasoning logically leads to universal salvation, which implies that Cassian was at least a hopeful universalist. [6]

The disciples of Chrysostom

    John Chrysostom, whose views I discussed in a previous post, had a wide influence in the Eastern church after him. Some of his students played a peripheral role in the first Origenist controversy and other events surrounding it. For example, Palladius, bishop of Helenopolis in the early fifth century, was a disciple of both Evagrius and Chrysostom. He highly praised both of these teachers and defended them against charges of heresy that had been raised by the anti-‘Origenist’ party (HL 38; Dialogue). His writings are primarily historical, so we can’t know whether he believed in the universal restoration, but given his Evagrian alliances it’s probable that he did.

    Another student of Chrysostom was Proclus, who became bishop of Constantinople from 434 to 446. He played a role in the Nestorian controversy of the mid-fifth century, supporting Cyril of Alexandria’s Christology over Nestorius’. The church historian Socrates praised Proclus for his positive attitude toward dead brethren, as opposed to Theophilus’ harsh treatment of the deceased Origen (EH VII.45), which suggests but doesn’t prove that Proclus had Origenian leanings. His writings mostly deal with Christology and Mariology, although Ramelli notes some indications in his homilies that he held to the universal restoration. [7] However, these passages may only indicate that he believed in universal atonement, not necessarily an actual universal restoration.

    Isidore of Pelusium was an ascetic and another student of Chrysostom, who supported him during his exile. In his many letters, he focuses on the importance of good works and takes little interest in theological controversies, although he supported a dyophysite and monoprosopic Christology, drawing on the work of Athanasius (letters 23, 303, 323, 405). He was accused of ‘Origenism’ in his lifetime by Severus of Antioch (Lib c imp Gram III.39), but it’s unclear whether he believed in the universal restoration. Overall, in line with Chrysostom’s own alliances, his disciples fell on the Origenian side of the fifth-century controversy.

Peter Chrysologus

    Peter was the bishop of Ravenna from 433 to 450. He delivered many theological and exegetical sermons during his time as bishop, which led to his title “Golden-Worded” (Chrysologus) and his popularity in his own day. Many of his sermons have survived to the present day. [8] In them, he speaks of future punishment in Gehenna (e.g., Hom 58.14; 60.16–17; 62.9, 13; 66; 121), but never describes it as “eternal” (aidios), and surprisingly only once describes it as aiōnios (50.3; cf. 52.2, in reference to demons). It is possible for souls to be saved from Gehenna by the intercession of the saints (123.8). In one sermon, he emphasizes that God, being impassible, does not become angry, but punishes as a medicine against the sickness of evil (Hom 45). Peter also inherits Origen’s interpretation of the parable of the lost sheep: this sheep refers to the whole human race in Adam, which was lost but restored through Christ’s incarnation, death, and resurrection (161.5–6). In light of this, it’s plausible (but not certain) that Peter Chrysologus held to the universal restoration.

Theodore of Mopsuestia

    Theodore was a student of Diodore of Tarsus and a key member of the so-called Antiochian school of theology. He was also a friend of John Chrysostom, and the two corresponded throughout their life (e.g., Chrysostom, Ad Theo laps; letter 204; 212). He became the bishop of Mopsuestia near Antioch from 392 to 428. Like his teacher Diodore, in his struggle against ‘Arianism’ and Apollinarism, he stressed the distinction between Christ’s two natures, which resulted in his Christology being viewed as ‘Nestorian’ after his death. Both he and Diodore were eventually condemned for their Christology, even though they were seen as orthodox theologians in their day.

    Diodore and Theodore were also both universalists, and were cited together as such in the writings of later Syriac theologians (e.g., Isaac of Nineveh, Second Part 39.8–13; John of Dara, On the Resurrection IV.21; Theodore bar Konai, Scholion II.63). In an excerpt preserved by Solomon of Basra (Book of the Bee 60), Theodore says that those who have chosen good will receive good in the next world, whereas the wicked will receive punishment until they have learned to choose the good, after which they will be found worthy of divine happiness. In support of this, he cites Matthew 5:26 and Luke 12:47–48, which in his view refer to potentially lengthy but still limited punishments. Like his teacher, Theodore defines aiōn not as eternity, but as “an interval of time, whether short or long” (Comm in Gal 1:4). He looks forward to the “future aeon” when all humans, indeed all rational beings, will harmoniously praise Christ (Comm in Eph 1:10).

Theodoret of Cyrrhus

    Theodoret was a student of Diodore of Tarsus and Theodore of Mopsuestia who became bishop of Cyrrhus near Antioch from 423 to 457. He also belonged to the Antiochian school of theology, and he initially defended Nestorius against Cyril of Alexandria’s anathemas, although he later condemned him at the Council of Chalcedon. Like the other members of the Antiochian school, his Christology was later suspected to be ‘Nestorian,’ and he was eventually posthumously condemned. Theodoret believed that God’s punishments are necessarily restorative, and so they cannot extend into eternity (Hom in Ezek VI.6; Comm in Isa XIII). His universalism is clear from his interpretation of 1 Corinthians 15:28:

“That God may be all in all.” God is already everywhere according to his essence, because his nature is unlimited, and “in him we live and move and have our being,” according to the divine apostle. But according to goodwill, he is not yet “in all.” For he delights in those who fear him, and in those who hope for his mercy. Yet even in these, he is not “all,” since no one is pure of contamination... But in the future life, when corruption ceases and immortality is given, passions will have no place. When these are completely driven out, no kind of sin will be committed anymore. In this way God will then be “all in all,” for all will be liberated from sin and will turn toward God, and there will be no fall into a worse state. (PG 82.360–61)

Theodoret offers the same interpretation in his commentary on Ephesians 1:23 (PG 82.517), where he says that God is not “all in all” because some people are impious and transgressors, but “in the future life” there will be no more possibility of sin.

Cyril of Alexandria

    Cyril was the nephew of Theophilus of Alexandria and the bishop of Alexandria from 412 to 444. He was an enormously influential theologian who helped settle the mid-5th century Nestorian controversy in favor of the anti-‘Nestorians’. He convened the Council of Ephesus in 431 before Nestorius and his supporters arrived, which predictably led to the condemnation of Nestorius. The resulting Christological conflict caused the first major split within Christianity, between the miaphysite Oriental Orthodox Church, the ‘Nestorian’ Church of the East, and the ‘Chalcedonian’ Catholic Church (which later split into the Roman Catholic and Eastern Orthodox Churches).

    Cyril’s main focus throughout his life was Christology, where he strongly emphasized the unity of Christ’s divine and human nature(s). Because the Logos was fully united to human nature, the whole humanity is united to Christ, and it can be truly said that in this sense all humans are in Christ; the purpose of the incarnation is “so that, having all in himself, he might reconcile all in one body to the Father [Col 1:20], as Paul says” (Comm in John 1:14). This universalistic language, absent any contextual qualifiers, is certainly suggestive of the universal restoration. Cyril believed in future punishment – for example, he says that the state of the wicked after the resurrection will be worse than death (Comm in John 3:36; cf. 8:51; 10:16; 11:25–27; 14:21; 19:30), and that the soul as well as the body will be punished (Serm in Luke 87) – as did every patristic universalist. As far as I can tell, he never describes these punishments as aidios (“eternal”), which he does use to describe Christ and future life, although he does call them ametros, “without measure” (Comm in John 19:30).

    Cyril knew that eis ton aiōna and aiōnios do not mean strictly “eternal,” since he interprets Jesus’ statement that those who believe in him will not die eis ton aiōna to mean that they will not die “in the future aeon” after the resurrection (Comm in John 8:51; 11:25–27). He clarifies, however, that there is no “limit” (peras) to the coming aeon (Comm in John 8:51). Even so, he does find a spiritual meaning of the Sabbath to refer to the rest of the saints at the “end [telei] of the aeons” (Comm in John 7:24). At the end of his discussion of the Sabbath, he says that this will be when passions and evil will cease, based on the work of Christ’s death, “that he might raise all to newness of life” (ibid.). This all sounds incredibly similar to Origen and/or Gregory of Nyssa, but even more suggestive is his commentary on 1 Cor 15:28:

[Christ] has annihilated the power of death and also eliminated the root of death, which is sin; he threw out the ruler of this world. After doing all this and bringing the whole salvific economy to completion, he will hand to the Father the Kingdom that once upon a time had been stolen from him and had passed under the power of others, so to exert his power over all beings on earth, after restoring them, having them return to himself, once he has annihilated death and satan, who had tyrannised them, the Son will have again, and for the world to come, the excellence of the power over all. [9]

Cyril also uses the language of universal restoration elsewhere in his commentary on John (e.g., Comm in John 8:20; 17:2). I’m not certain if this means that he was a universalist – he may be using hyperbole in these passages – but I find it probable.

Conclusion

    The turn of the fifth century saw the outbreak of an Origenist controversy, brought on largely by the misunderstandings of Origen’s actual views spread by Epiphanius. At this stage, the universal restoration of humans wasn’t in dispute, only the restoration of the devil. However, the outsize influence of Augustine popularized anti-universalism in the West, with even the limited purgatory proposed by Jerome (‘universal salvation’ of Christians) being rejected. Even so, universalism – at least hopeful universalism – retained a few proponents in the West, Paulinus of Nola and John Cassian. The concept of universal restoration (of at least humans) remained semipopular in the East, propounded by the theologians of the Antiochian school (Theodore of Mopsuestia, Theodoret of Cyrrhus) and arguably Cyril of Alexandria.

______________________________

[1] Why didn’t Rufinus cite more fathers than this, since there were other universalist teachers in the early church? I think it’s likely that he’s specifically citing those fathers who believed in the eventual restoration of the devil, since that was the main point of contention between him and Jerome, although this still doesn’t explain why he didn’t cite Gregory of Nyssa, who also believed in the restoration of the devil.

[2] See especially György Hedel, The Influence of Origen on the Young Augustine: A Chaper in the History of Origenism (Piscataway, NJ: Gorgias Press, 2009); Ilaria L. E. Ramelli, “Origen in Augustine: A Paradoxical Reception,” Numen 60 (2013): 280–307.

[3] Hedel, The Influence of Origen, 189–93; Ramelli, The Christian Doctrine of Apokatastasis, 663–64.

[4] Furthermore, this supports our reading of the earlier church fathers. If – as a minority of scholars implausibly maintain – not even Gregory of Nyssa was a universalist, then who could this “large majority” possibly consist of? But if universalism had become a dominant tradition within the Eastern church, this statement from Augustine makes sense (as does Jerome’s statement in ca. 400 that “most” believe in the eventual restoration of the devil).

[5] For an overview see Brian Daley, The Hope of the Early Church: A Handbook of Patristic Eschatology (Cambridge University Press, 1991), 124–167, 205–215. Pope Leo I (440–461) is representative of Latin eschatology in this period: “In the underworld there is no correction, nor is any substitute for retributive suffering possible when the activity of the will no longer remains” (Serm 35.4).

[6] Ramelli, The Christian Doctrine of Apokatastasis, 681–86.

[7] Ramelli, The Christian Doctrine of Apokatastasis, 570–71.

[8] English translations of these sermons are available in three volumes of the Fathers of the Church series published by the Catholic University of America Press.

[9] Translation by Ramelli, The Christian Doctrine of Apokatastasis, 599–600.

The Restoration of All: Universalism in Early Christianity (part 7)

Part 6: Fourth Century Fathers (1/2)

Fourth Century Fathers (part 2)

    In my last post, we looked at the eschatological views of some fourth-century church fathers regarding the ultimate fate of unbelievers (i.e., those who fail to believe in Christ in this life). Due to the sheer number of church fathers from this period and the volume of data, I had to split them up into two posts. In this post, we’ll look at the views of eight more church fathers from the late fourth century, leading up to the first Origenist controversy that broke out at the turn of the fifth century.

Basil of Caesarea

    Basil “the Great” was the bishop of Caesarea in Cappadocia from 370 to 379. Together with Gregory of Nazianzus and his brother Gregory of Nyssa, he is one of the so-called “Cappadocian Fathers” who deeply influenced later Christian theology. His grandmother Macrina the Elder studied under Gregory Thaumaturgus, who was himself a disciple of Origen. Basil had a deep respect for both of these teachers (Letter 28; 204.6; De Spir Sanct 29.73–74), and together with Gregory of Nazianzus, he compiled an anthology of Origen’s writings called the Philocalia. Included among these excerpts is a list of prooftexts supporting the restorative nature of God’s punishments (XXVII.6–9), along with texts on rational creatures’ freedom of choice (XI) and the ontological non-subsistence of evil (XXIV.3–7). Basil himself certainly believed that evil is a privation (e.g., God is Not the Author of Evil).

    In a short passage from Basil’s Regulae, a question is posed: if some will be punished with many blows and some with few (Lk 12:47), how can some people say that there is no end to punishment? The response cites several passages that speak of aeonian punishment (Matt 25:41, 46; Mk 9:43–48; Isa 66:24), and says,

But due to a deception of the devil, many people, as though they forgot these and similar statements of the Lord, adhere to the conception of the end of punishment, out of an audacity that is even superior to their sin. For if at a certain moment there is an end to aeonian punishment, aeonian life will certainly have an end as well. And if we do not admit of thinking this concerning life, what reason should there be for assigning an end to aeonian punishment? (Regulae 267)

    The ferocity with which this passage condemns the idea of an end to aeonian punishment is surprising, especially considering Basil’s admiration of Origen and Gregory Thaumaturgus. Basil says of his own brother Gregory of Nyssa (who was certainly a universalist) that he wishes he could be the leader of “the whole Church under the sun,” if that were possible (Letter 98.2). It seems odd that he would say that his brother, whom he held in such great esteem, is deceived by the devil. Basil knew that aiōn doesn’t mean strictly eternal (although, to be fair, he doesn’t explicitly say the same about aiōnios) – he says that “some attribute to the aeons [aiōnes] the description of eternal [tou aidiou],” but he himself rejects this view (Contra Eunomium II.17) – and he uses aidios (“eternal”) to describe future life, but not punishment. [1] Given his familiarity with Origen, he also would have known Origen’s argument that life and death cannot be coeternal (Comm in Rom V.7.8), yet he makes no attempt to refute it here. In light of all this, it seems at least plausible that (as Ramelli argues) this passage is not authentic.

    Basil’s commentary on Isaiah, which is likely authentic, clearly supports universal restoration. In this work, he frequently speaks of the restorative nature of punishment: “God is angry in this way, so that he may benefit sinners. For he does not chastise for destruction, but instructs for correction” (Comm in Isa I.54–59; cf. V.179–181; VI.183–186; VII.195; IX.230–231; X.242–244; XVI.306). This is true also of the “fire of the aeon to come,” which will purify those who have sinned “unto death” (IV.137). Even God’s warning that he will not forgive his people “is not a harmful threat, but an instruction preparatory to bringing salvation” (II.84). Commenting on Isaiah 9:7, he says,

The peace from the Lord is co-extensive with all eternity, since it is unlimited and boundless. For all beings will be subjected to him and all will recognize his mastery, and when God will be “all in all,” and those making an uproar by their apostasies are pacified, all in peaceful harmony will praise God with hymns. (IX.226; cf. VIII.222; XVI.306)

This is in line with what Basil writes in his undisputed works. In his Hexaemeron, he states that the world was created “for a useful end and for the great advantage of all beings... the training ground where they learn to know God” (I.6). Basil even considers that “possibly,” the devil himself was able to repent after he sinned, but “maybe” this possibility has since been precluded (Comm in Isa XIV.279).

    An important testimony to Basil’s views is provided by the fifth-century church historian Orosius. In his work Against the Priscillianists and the Origenists, he says that “Saint Basil the Greek” taught several Origenian doctrines “in the most holy way,” even though “they were not correct as I [Orosius] now understand.” One of these doctrines is that “eternal fire” describes the torment of the sinner’s conscience, and this fire is not endless because “eternal [aeternum] according to its Greek etymology [i.e., aiōnios] does not mean unending [perpetuum],” for which he appeals to Scriptural usage. Therefore, the souls of all sinners will be purified and “return to the unity of the body of Christ,” and possibly even the substance of the rational being that became the devil (which is not in itself evil) will be saved. [2] This testimony is clear and shows that Basil was probably a universalist.

Gregory of Nazianzus

    Gregory of Nazianzus was the close friend of Basil, one of the “Cappadocian Fathers,” and the bishop of Constantinople from 380 to 381. He presided over the Council of Constantinople in 381 which defined trinitarian orthodoxy and promulgated the Niceno-Constantinopolitan Creed. Together with Basil he compiled the Philocalia, an anthology of Origen’s writings. This Philocalia includes a number of texts on freedom of choice (XI), the ontological non-subsistence of evil (XXIV.3–7), and the restorative nature of God’s punishment (XXVII.6–9). The Nazianzen even describes Origen as “the whetstone of us all.”

     Gregory was definitely a universalist, as I will show, but he held strongly to the ‘doctrine of reserve’ which Origen also held (e.g., Contra Celsum VI.26): that certain truths (including universal restoration) should be held from new or spiritually weak believers. This concern can be seen in his Oration 40.45 (where, it should be noted, one of the basic doctrines of the faith is that “evil has no substance or kingdom, either unoriginate or self-existent or created by God”). Gregory speaks of “the worm which devours eternally [aidiōs],” which he represents as a nightmare of a sinner’s guilty conscience, sent by God as a “medicine for salvation” (Carm mor 7.191–199 [PG 37.662–3]). This is the only place where he describes punishment as “eternal” (aidios), and it shows his understanding of the importance of threats.

    In one of Gregory’s sermons to the people of Nazianzus, delivered in 373, he emphasizes the cleansing nature of punishment in this world, to which he contrasts the future punishments, which “is the time of punishment, not cleansing”; even here he interprets these punishments not as physical, but as being cast out from God and having a guilty conscience (Orat 16.6–9). In another sermon, delivered in 381, he distinguishes between the cleansing fire that burns away evil and the future fire “which is not cleansing, but avenging... unless someone prefers to think, even in this case, that this fire is applied out of love for humans, in a way worthy of the one who punishes” (40.36). Here he stops just short of affirming that this is true; but in other sermons, speaking of the punishment of physical death, he says,

Here too he [i.e., the human] makes a gain: death, and the cutting off of sin, so that evil should not be immortal. Thus punishment became an act of love for humanity; for I am persuaded that this is the way in which God punishes. (Orat 38.7; 45.8)

In both places, Gregory speaks of God’s punishment being out of love for humanity (philanthrōpia), and in the latter he confirms that this is his own view. Moreover, he adopts the same interpretation of the curse of physical death as Origen and others, that it was instituted so that sin and evil would not be eternal. Elsewhere he also takes a purifying view of the future punishment, which he refers to as the baptism of fire, “that extreme baptism, which is more painful and longer, which consumes matter like straw and the lightness of all evil” (39.15, 19).

    In a poem, he says that in the next life people will either meet fire or God; “but will all [partake of] God later on? Let this be established elsewhere” (De se ipso 544–546 [PG 37.1010]). Once again, Gregory stops just short of affirming this, although he did just describe the eschatological fire as purifying (De se ipso 522–525). See also his Oration 45.24, where he urges his listeners to consider whether Christ descended to hades “to save all men absolutely... or there, too, only those who believe.” In his theological sermon on the Son, he says,

God will be “all in all” in the time of restoration, when we will no longer be many, as we are now, with movements of the will and passions, and we will not have in us little or nothing of God, but we will all be entirely conformed to God, able to receive God wholly and alone. This is the perfection to which we aspire, and it is above all Paul who guarantees this. (Orat 30.5–6)

This will be precisely because of the Son’s incarnation and sacrifice. It’s because of his suffering that “all of us, not just some and not the others, have been restored; all of us who partake of the same Adam, and were deceived by the serpent and killed by sin, have been saved by the heavenly Adam” (Orat 33.9). Finally, during Rufinus’ and Jerome’s dispute over Origen, they both agreed that Gregory of Nazianzus was in fact a universalist (Rufinus, Apology Against Jerome I.43). Based on this, we can be sure that he was a universalist, albeit one who employed the ‘doctrine of reserve’ liberally.

Gregory of Nyssa

    Gregory of Nyssa was the third “Cappadocian Father” who was bishop of Nyssa from 372 to 394, and with his brothers played an important role in shaping later Christian theology. Gregory came to be highly venerated in the later church; at the Council of Nicaea II in 787, it was declared that “all have called [him] the Father of Fathers”. He was also the most overtly universalist of the three Cappadocians, to the extent that after universalism fell out of favor in the church, his works were thought to have been changed and interpolated by ‘Origenists’ (e.g., Photius, Bibliotheca 233). His eschatological views resound all throughout his works, but especially In Illud (his commentary on 1 Cor 15) and On the Soul and the Resurrection (written in remembrance of his late brother Basil).

    In his comments on 1 Cor 15:28, Gregory is unequivocal:

What therefore does Paul teach us? It consists in saying that evil will come to nothing and be completely destroyed. The divine, pure goodness will contain in itself every rational nature; no being created by God will be excluded from his kingdom, once everything mixed with some elements of base material has been consumed by refinement in fire. Such things had their origin in God; what was made in the beginning did not receive evil. Paul says this is so. (14)

He appeals to the fact that evil is a privation, and every rational nature is ontologically good, which he says is supported by Paul (17); therefore, if evil is destroyed, every being will be left with the Good alone, that is, God.

    Moreover, this will take place thanks to the Son’s incarnation: in this act he assumed “the entire human nature,” so “it is through this man that all humanity is joined to the Divinity.” “Christ’s body, as it is often said, consists of human nature in its entirety, to which he has been united” (21). Right now, only some people are united to him through faith, but eventually “all creation resounds as one voice, when every being in heaven, on earth and under the earth [Phil 2:10]... has become one body and is joined in Christ through obedience to one another... faith means that no being will be outside the saved” (18–21). In his exegesis of 1 Cor 15:24–28, he also distinguishes four types of “subjection” in Scripture, and shows that only the last type – salvation (Ps 62:1 LXX) – could possibly apply here, lest the subjection of the Son be degrading as the “heretics” claim (4–7; cf. Contra Eunomium II.14). Therefore, he concludes,

When all enemies have become God’s footstool, they will receive a trace of divinity in themselves. Once death has been destroyed... then we will be subjected to him; but this is not understood by some sort of servile humility. Our subjection, however, consists of a kingdom, incorrupt­ibility and blessedness living in us; this is Paul’s meaning of being subjected to God. (23)

Thus, Gregory of Nyssa presents three intertwined arguments – philosophical, Christological, and exegetical – for universal salvation in In Illud.

    In On the Soul and the Resurrection, which is presented as a philosophical discourse between Gregory and his sister Macrina the Younger, there is more of a focus on the purifying nature of punishment. Those who fail to divest themselves of evil in this life will have to be purified in the next; it will be more painful the more a soul attaches itself to evil, but this is out of “love for humanity,” to drag all creatures to God (97–100). The parable of Dives and Lazarus is interpreted in this way (81–89). The purpose of this is to annihilate evil: “since evil does not exist in nature, outside of will, once each will has come to be in God evil will be reduced to complete disappearance, since no receptacle will be left for it... as the Apostle says, God will be ‘all in all’” (100–105). Phil 2:9–11 is interpreted as referring to the universal restoration, and the Feast of Tabernacles is seen as foreshadowing it (132–136).

    This is found all throughout Gregory’s writings. In his On the Life of Moses, he interprets the three days of darkness over Egypt followed by light as the eventual restoration of those who are punished in Gehenna (II.82–83). In his Catechetical Oration, he argues strongly that Christ’s incarnation and death secured the benefit and healing of all people, and even “the originator of evil [i.e., the devil] himself,” although some will require painful chastisement until “a harmony of thanksgiving arises from all creation” (26). In his last work, the Homilies on the Song of Songs, he says that God will achieve his will for “all to be saved” (IV; cf. 1 Tim 2:4), and he concludes his homilies with a reference to the universal restoration (XV).

    Gregory of Nyssa gives fearful descriptions of aeonian punishment in various places (e.g., Hom in Beat V.8), and was not afraid to use it as a threat (Hom in Song pref. 12; I.16), but does not describe it as “eternal” (aidios). He was well aware of the distinction in terminology, since in his argument against the ‘Arian’ Eunomius, he says that “the eternal [aidios] existence... is not measured by ages [aiōsi]” (Contra Eunomium I.41) Thus, he was clearly a universalist. [3]

Evagrius Ponticus

    Evagrius Ponticus was a prominent monk and theologian in the late 4th century, one of the most influential of the Desert Fathers. He was ordained by Basil of Caesarea and studied under Gregory of Nazianzus and Gregory of Nyssa (Palladius, HL 38.2), so he was steeped in the trinitarian and eschatological thought of the Cappadocians. In fact, his trinitarian views were so close to those of the Cappadocians that his own letter On the Faith was misattributed to Basil. In this letter, he interprets various New Testament texts in order to refute ‘Arianism’ and other trinitarian heresies. One such text is 1 Cor 15:24–28, which is interpreted to refer to the restoration, “when God, who is one, comes to be in each one and unifies all, so that the number is lost in the indwelling of unity” (7); and the subjection of the enemies is interpreted as salvific (8).

    Evagrius died just before the outbreak of the Origenist controversy, but he was later accused by Jerome of being an ‘Origenist’ (Letter 133.3). Indeed, he inherited many aspects of Origen’s thought via the Cappadocians, and seems to have taken them in a more extreme direction. He begins his magnum opus, the Kephalaia Gnostica (“Chapters on Knowledge”), by proving the ontological non-subsistence of evil, which has its origin in the movement of the created wills (I.1–2, 39–41, 51, 89). No being is therefore evil in itself, not even the demons (III.53, 59; IV.59). It is because of this that evil will eventually disappear:

There was when evil did not exist, and there will be when it no longer exists, but there was never when virtue did not exist and there will never be when it does not exist, for the seeds of virtue are indestructible. (Keph Gnos I.40)

    Even the rich man in hell still possesses seeds of virtue, for he felt compassion (which is a virtue) for his brothers (I.40; cf. Lk 16:28). When evil is eliminated, so too will ignorance be from all rational beings, since “ignorance is the shadow of evil” (IV.29). Both paradise and hell are for the instruction of rational beings, the former for the righteous and the latter for the unrighteous (VI.8; cf. III.9; VI.76); one day both groups, represented as children, will reach adulthood (IV.15). This will be when Christ subjects all enemies under his feet, since subjection is salvific (VI.15; cf. Sch in Ps 21.29); then “all the natures of the rational beings will prostrate before the name of the Lord,” for which Evagrius cites Ps 85:9 and Phil 2:9–11 (VI.27). Evagrius takes precisely the same view of the aeons that Origen did; they are natural periods, at the end of each being a resurrection and judgment, set up to instruct rational beings in the knowledge of God (III.36, 38; VI.67). The universal restoration will then take place at the end of the aeons, after which there will be no more aeon (IV.38; V.89; VI.33–34).

    Evagrius, however, had a more extreme view of the restoration than Origen or the Cappadocians. This can be seen in his “great letter” to Melania the Elder, another influential ascetic and Desert Mother, in which he says,

And there will be a time when the body, the soul, and the intellect will cease to be separate from one another, with their names and their plurality, since the body and the soul will be elevated to the rank of intellect, in accordance with the words, “That they may be one in us, just as you and I are one.” Thus there will be a time when the Father, the Son, and the Spirit, and his rational creation, which constitutes his body, will cease to be separate, with their names and their plurality. And this conclusion can be drawn from the words, “God will be all in all.” (Ep ad Mel 22)

Like many other fathers, Evagrius believes that the entire rational creation constitutes Christ’s body and cites 1 Cor 15:24–28 along with John 17:21–23 to describe the universal restoration. However, he also believes that the final state will be an entirely incorporeal one, without bodies, unlike those other fathers (including Origen, who thought that created beings are inherently corporeal). [4] This is because, in his view, rational creatures were first incorporeal and bodies came after the fall (Ep ad Mel 26; cf. Keph Gnos VI.20). Furthermore, the entire rational creation will be subsumed into the Trinity; the hypostases of Father, Son, and Spirit will remain distinct, since they had no beginning, but creatures will become “one nature” with God (Ep ad Mel 23–30). Evagrius’ nearly pantheistic view of the restoration comes a step closer to the ‘Origenism’ that was condemned in the sixth century.

Cyril of Jerusalem

    Cyril was the bishop of Jerusalem from ca. 350 to 386, and was exiled from his see by ‘Arian’ leaders twice during this period. His main surviving work is a series of catechetical lectures given to those in Jerusalem around the time of their baptism, possibly toward the beginning of his episcopate. In these lectures, he frequently talks about the importance of faith and repentance for salvation (esp. Cat Lect 2). The Lord saved the thief on the cross after just an hour of faith, and he doesn’t desire sinners to perish, so no one should despair of their salvation (2.5, 19; 5.9–10). Repentance is even “able to quench the fires of hell,” as shown by the story of Daniel’s companions in the furnace (2.16). Faith is so strong that it is even able to save others, in certain cases, as shown by the stories of the paralytic and Lazarus (5.8–9); thus, Cyril offers an intercessory prayer for all sinners, even those who died in their sins (23.8–10).

    Whether Cyril believed in the universal restoration is difficult to say. He says in one place that repentance is impossible after death (18.14), but the passages cited above suggest that this may only be a hortatory threat (the universalist Gregory of Nazianzus gave a similar warning in Orat 16.7). He says that sinners are resurrected with different bodies to endure aeonian punishment (4.31; 18.19); but the same was held by Origen, Evagrius, and other universalists.

    Cyril believes in freedom of choice, that evil is a privation of the will, and that all rational beings, including the devil, were created good (2.1–4; 4.19–21). He claims that Adam’s curse was intended as restorative, “that seeing from where he had fallen, and from what and into what a state he was brought down, he may be saved by repentance” (2.7). In his comments on 1 Cor 15:24–28, he says that the subjection of the enemies and the Son is not to be interpreted as “perishing,” nor “a forced obedience, but a self-chosen accordance” (15.29–30). Moreover, the Church “brings the whole of humanity into subjection to the Divinity” (18.22). However, Cyril’s remarks are unfortunately not clear enough to say whether he was a universalist or an infernalist.

Diodore of Tarsus

    Diodore was a fourth-century theologian who founded a catechetical school at Antioch and was appointed bishop of Tarsus by Basil of Caesarea, where he stayed from 378 to 390. He was influential in his day and played a significant role in the 381 Council of Constantinople, but his Christology later came to be seen as ‘Nestorian,’ and he was condemned together with his pupil Theodore of Mopsuestia over a century later. Diodore was known to have been a universalist, and was cited as one by later theologians in the Syriac church, where his writings were preserved (e.g., Isaac of Nineveh, Second Part 39.12–13; John of Dara, On the Resurrection IV.21; Theodore bar Konai, Scholion II.63). Solomon of Basra provides us with two lengthy excerpts from Diodore, in which he argues that the unrighteous will be tormented in proportion to their sins before entering into blessedness, and shows from Scriptural usage that aiōnios does not mean unending (Book of the Bee 60).

    This is consistent with what we read in Diodore’s surviving commentary on the Psalms. There he says that God does everything for our benefit through “providence,” including punishment (Comm in Ps 4:4; 39:11). God is both good and just, therefore his punishments are restorative (25:8–10). He’s well aware that aiōn and aiōnios don’t refer strictly to an unending duration, since “it is customary with Scripture to call temporary things ‘aeonian’” (48:8; cf. 24:7). Diodore interprets subjection to the Lord as a joyful and happy submission (2:9–11), and says that ultimately all people will be subjected (45:4–5). The Logos, by taking the human nature, bestowed a common benefit upon the whole humanity (8:4).

John Chrysostom

    John Chrysostom was a student of Diodore of Tarsus and the archbishop of Constantinople from 397 to 403. He had a deep respect for his teacher, as is evident from the panegyric that he delivered for Diodore (Laus Diodori). During the Origenist controversy, he received four Origenian monks known as the “Tall Brothers” who had been banished from Egypt by the anti-‘Origenist’ Theophilus of Alexandria. John’s enemies, including Theophilus, managed to get him banished from his episcopate, and he died in exile. Palladius, who was a friend and disciple of both Evagrius and John Chrysostom, wrote a Dialogue in defense of him, in which the intrigue that led to his downfall is described. He has been posthumously vindicated, since he’s now regarded as one of three Ecumenical Teachers in Eastern Orthodoxy and a Doctor of the Church in Catholicism.

    John’s Origenian alliances during his life suggest that he wasn’t vehemently opposed to universalism, but within his writings, he indicates that he himself was an infernalist. In his homily on 2 Thess 1:8, he refers to “the retribution that is immortal, the chastisement that is eternal [aidios],” although he does present this as a threat which is a “wholesome medicine” meant to lead to repentance (PG 62.476–80). He continues,

There are many men who place their hopes, not in abstaining from sins, but in thinking that Gehenna is not so terrible as it is said to be, but milder than what is threatened, and temporary, not aeonian, and about this they philosophize much. But I could show from many reasons, and conclude from the very words of Scripture concerning Gehenna, that it is not only not milder, but much more terrible than is threatened. But I do not now intend to discourse concerning these things. For the fear even from bare words is sufficient, though we do not fully unfold their meaning. But that it is not temporary, hear Paul now saying, concerning those who know not God, and who do not believe in the Gospel, that “they shall suffer the punishment of aeonian destruction.” How then is that temporary which is aeonian? (PG 62.479)

In this passage, John acknowledges a “temporary” view of Gehenna and explicitly rejects it. [Although there are some oddities here: no patristic universalist ever claimed that punishment was not “aeonian,” nor did they ever claim that this provided a license to sin (on the contrary, they recognized the importance of threats). Furthermore, he uses “aeonian” in a sense that implies “endless,” but as a disciple of Diodore, he would have known that this isn’t necessarily the meaning of aiōnios.]

    In his homily on 1 Corinthians 3:12–15, John Chrysostom offers the question: “How is the rule of justice preserved, if punishment has no end?” In response, he says, “When God has established something, obey his decisions and do not submit what is said to human reasoning.” In order to refute the restorative interpretation of 1 Cor 3:12–15, he interprets Paul’s words, “he shall be saved,” as referring to perpetual damnation in fire (Hom in 1 Cor 9.5–6). Later in the same series of homilies, he says, “retribution will not be such as to have a limit and be abolished, but the chastisement will be aeonian” (Hom in 1 Cor 23.5). Once again, he uses “aeonian” in a sense that clearly implies “endless.”

    Although John believes in endless punishment, he also believes that the prayers and almsgiving of the saints can mitigate the punishments of those who died in sin (e.g., Hom in Phil 3; Hom in Acts 21). When comforting believers who have lost loved ones, he addresses the objection, “It is on this very account that I lament, because he died while he was in sin!” In response, he says that the believer should rejoice, since his loved one’s “sins have been broken off and have stopped adding iniquities”; furthermore, he can help them by prayer and almsgiving. John continues,

Let us not be weary in giving aid to the dead and praying for them. For the purification of the whole world [tēs oikoumenēs] is expected. Therefore we pray with confidence for the whole world, and mention them along with the martyrs, the confessors, and the priests. For all of us are one body, although some members are more glorious than others, and it is possible to put together forgiveness for them in every way, with prayers, gifts offered on their behalf, and thanks to those who are mentioned with them. Why therefore do you grieve and complain, since it is in your power to put together so great a forgiveness for the dead? (Hom in 1 Cor 41.5)

In this passage, John says that the whole world – including those who died in their sins, along with the martyrs and confessors – is one body, and is expected to be purified. Finally, in his homilies on Colossians, when Paul says that Christ is the head of the church, John interprets, “when he says ‘church’ he means the whole of humanity” (Hom in Col 3). He continues, commenting on Paul’s statement that Christ reconciles all things to God: “He who is the head of the church says not only, ‘Peace to you,’ but ‘Peace to all,’” for unless all members of the body are at peace, there is no peace (paraphrase). This suggests that John Chrysostom believed in both an eschatological universalism and in the reality of endless punishment, but that every human would avoid the latter through the prayer and almsgiving of the saints.

Ambrose of Milan

    Ambrose was the bishop of Milan in Italy from 374 to 397 and a staunch anti-‘Arian’. In his day he was highly influential, a friend of the Roman emperor Theodosius I who even gave the eulogy at his funeral. He was also very knowledgeable in Greek and highly influenced by Origen. His views were so close to Origen’s in some respects that Jerome accused him of translating portions of Origen’s works into Latin and passing them off as his own (Rufinus, Apology Against Jerome II.23, 25). Among other things, Ambrose inherited his universalistic interpretation of 1 Cor 15:24–28, as is evident from his interpretation of this passage in On the Faith:

When therefore all beings have become subject to Christ, through Christ’s obedience, so that all bend their knees in his name, then he himself will be all in all. For now, since all do not believe, all do not seem to be in subjection. But when all have believed and done the will of God, then Christ will be all in all. And when Christ is all in all, then will God be all in all; for the Father ever abides in the Son. (De fide V.15.182)

This is the conclusion to Ambrose’s lengthy exegesis of the passage (De fide V.13–15), in which he argues that “subjection” refers to voluntary obedience, that Christ’s body is the whole of humanity, and so Christ’s subjection (in his created nature) cannot occur until every person believes and is saved. As he said earlier in this work, “the mystery of the incarnation of God is the salvation of the whole creation,” by which he means “every creature,” in support of which he cites Heb 2:9 and Rom 8:21 (De fide V.8.105). This is all in order to refute the ‘Arian’ interpretation which degrades the Son.

    Ambrose held that evil is a privation, and that every creature (qua created by God) is good (De Isaac vel anima 7.60–61; 8.79). Moreover, like other Origenian universalists, he believed that physical death can be considered a good since it prevents sin and guilt from becoming eternal; he devoted an entire work to this topic (De bono mortis; cf. De sacramentis II.6.17). In his commentary on Psalm 118, he says that human sinners will pass through a baptism of fire to burn up their sins, in contrast to the devil and his angels who will be there everlastingly (Exp in Ps 118 3.14–17).

    Ambrose, like every other patristic universalist including Gregory of Nyssa, holds that punishments occur in the next world, and that those who receive excessive temporal goods in this life will tend to receive punishment in the next (De officis I.15–16). He refers to the result of blasphemy of the Holy Spirit as aeternus punishment (De Spir Sanct I.3.53), and recognizes the usefulness of the threat of aeternus punishment (De officis I.33.188). As a follower of Origen and proficient in Greek, he surely would have known that aeternus in this case is translated from aiōnios and not aidios (see the comments of Orosius on Basil above). Ambrose, however, does seem to say in one place that the punishment of the devil will have no end (De fide II.13.118), which implies that he only believed in the universal restoration of humans.

Conclusion

    In the late fourth century, universalism appears to have increased further in popularity. All three of the “Cappadocian Fathers” (at least the two Gregories) were probably universalists, and were recognized as such by later church fathers. Their student Evagrius Ponticus inherited their trinitarian theology and universalist eschatology, in an even more extreme form (with a nearly pantheistic view of the restoration). Cyril of Jerusalem’s views aren’t entirely clear, but he certainly shared many views with the patristic universalists. Diodore of Tarsus, who founded the catechetical school of Antioch, was definitely a universalist, and his disciple John Chrysostom was an infernalist (but plausibly held an eschatological universalism based on the intercession of the saints). Finally, Ambrose of Milan was one of the first fathers to bring Origen’s views – including his universalism – to the West.

______________________________

[1] Ramelli and Konstan, Terms for Eternity, 189–99.

[2] Ilaria L. E. Ramelli, “Basil and Apokatastasis: New Findings,” Journal of Early Christian History 4 (2014): 116–21.

[3] Unfortunately, due to limitations of space, I couldn’t fully flesh out Gregory’s ideas, but see Ramelli, The Christian Doctrine of Apokatastasis, 372–440 for a fuller overview of his universalism. I also strongly recommend reading Gregory of Nyssa’s Great Catechism for an exposition of his wider views.

[4] Although see Gregory of Nazianzus, Oration 7.21, where he speaks of the body and the soul becoming “one in spirit and intellect [nous] and deity [theos], the mortal and mutable being swallowed up by life” in the resurrection.

The Restoration of All: Universalism in Early Christianity (part 6)

Part 5: Third-Century Fathers

Fourth Century Fathers (part 1)

    In the past few posts, we’ve examined the views of all the major church fathers about the final destiny of unbelievers up to the beginning of the fourth century. It’s clear that there was no widespread consensus on this topic, although universalism virtually became the consensus of the eastern church during the third century. Now let’s look at the views of the church during the first half of the fourth century. At this time, the spotlight was on Christological and trinitarian issues, not eschatology, although these issues were intertwined (as we’ll see).

Eusebius of Caesarea

    Eusebius was the bishop of Caesarea in Palestine from ca. 314 to 339. He was a student of Pamphilus, his predecessor as bishop, who was also a staunch supporter of Origen; together they wrote a five-book defense of Origen’s theology (see the last post in this series). Pamphilus’ influence on him was so great that he even referred to himself as Eusebius “of Pamphilus.” Eusebius is best known as the author of a ten-book Church History, for which he is titled “Father of Church History.” However, he was also a theologian in his own right, who played a large role in the conflict surrounding the AD 325 Council of Nicaea. In fact, he presented his own formula of faith at that council, which (after some minor additions) became the first edition of the Nicene Creed! [1] But because he came to be viewed as a ‘subordinationist’ rather than an orthodox trinitarian, his theological views were suppressed, even though he was canonized as a saint. [2]

    Eusebius had a deep respect for Origen, which he inherited from his teacher and predecessor. In his Church History, he considered the entire life of Origen to be worth reporting, “even so to speak from his swaddling clothes” (VI.2.2). One of the doctrines that Eusebius drew from him was his universalist reading of 1 Corinthians 15:24–28, which he expounds toward the end of his Church Theology:

[I]n the meantime [before the telos], seeing as [the enemies] are not worthy of this, having taken upon himself, like a common Savior of all, the correction of the imperfect and care of those in need of healing, he exercises his kingship, putting the enemies of the kingdom under his feet... When he places the enemies under his feet, he will, however, establish those worthy of his kingdom in everlasting life, for at that time even death, the last enemy of all, will be destroyed. For when no one dies anymore, and those who are worthy of the kingdom will live in eternal life, death, of course, will no longer exist, since it will no longer have anyone to kill. When these have been suitably prepared, all holy ones will be subjected with a saving subjection to the Son of God... After the consummation of all things, when the new age has come, he will no longer dwell in some few of them, but in all, who are then worthy of the kingdom of heaven. Thus in this way he will be “all in all”. (Ecc Theol III.15–16)

    Here we see Eusebius’ belief that the punishment of Christ’s enemies during his reign will be corrective; that the subjection of the enemies is a “saving subjection”; and that at the telos, God will no longer dwell “in some few of them, but in all,” who will be made worthy. Compare Origen’s statement that “not only in some few or in many, but in all God will be all” (De Princ III.6.3). Eusebius presents this interpretation in the context of his polemic against Marcellus of Ancyra, who postulated an end to Christ’s human reign based on this passage. In response, he answers that the subjection in 1 Cor 15 is not forced, nor a unification in which personal identity is confused, but “the obedience that comes from free choice and the glory and honor that all beings will give to him as Savior and King of all” (Ecc Theol III.15.5). The Father will dwell in all who are ruled by the Son, so that all people are unified in “community of glory” with the Trinity (III.18–19).

    This same view is found across Eusebius’ other writings. In his comments on the Transfiguration account in Luke, he says that in the end, “it will no longer be as before when only three disciples... fell on their faces in fear, but ‘every knee will bend in heaven and on earth and under the earth.’” In his comments on Isaiah 25, in line with the Septuagint reading, he interprets the punishment as purificatory and, ultimately, resulting in the restoration of humanity; the final destruction will belong to “death” and “evil demon[s],” not humanity. Eusebius frequently uses the Greek term aidios (“eternal”) to refer to eschatological life, but only the term aiōnios (“aeonian”) to refer to punishment, in line with the Scriptural usage. [3] Based on this, we can confidently say that he was a universalist.

Marcellus of Ancyra

    Marcellus was the bishop of Ancyra in the early to mid fourth century, and he played a large role in the post-Nicene theological conflicts. [4] He fought alongside Athanasius of Alexandria against the ‘Arians,’ but his views were later condemned for falling into the opposite heresy of modalism. Furthermore, based on his interpretation of 1 Corinthians 15:24–28, he believed that Christ’s human reign would eventually end (although God would continue to reign through his Logos). This doctrine was staunchly opposed by Eusebius of Caesarea and others, whose view ultimately won out, resulting in the addition of the phrase “whose kingdom will have no end” to the Nicene Creed.

    Despite his dispute with Eusebius over modalism and the telos of Christ’s reign, these two theological heavyweights of the fourth century appear to have agreed on the universal restoration. Eusebius quotes Marcellus as saying,

What else does the phrase “until the time for restoration” wish to convey to us than the coming age, in which all beings must be completely restored?... [I]n the time of the restoration of absolutely all [apantōn], even creation itself will pass from bondage to liberty, for [Paul] says that “the creation itself will be set free from its bondage to decay and obtain the glorious liberty of the sons of God” (Contra Marcellum II.4.11)

    Based on the surviving fragments of Marcellus’ Contra Asterium, he – like Origen – saw Christ’s body as uniting the whole of fallen humanity, for the purpose of restoring that humanity (frags. 107, 111, 113 Klostermann). [5] Because the Logos assumed humanity for this purpose (and not for himself), when all of his enemies have been subjected and all beings are restored, there will be no need for him to remain incarnate (117 Klostermann). If the disputed work De Incarnatione et contra Arianos was written by Marcellus, this provides an even more explicitly universalist reading of 1 Cor 15:24–28, where subjection is clearly interpreted as salvific and all humans, including those who are now enemies, are said to become full members of Christ’s body (19). [5]

Athanasius of Alexandria

    Athanasius was the bishop of Alexandria throughout the mid fourth century. During this time, he violently opposed ‘Arianism’ to the extent that he was accused of murder at one point. Despite his controversy in his own day, he came to be seen as the hero of the post-Nicene conflicts, titled “Pillar of the Church” and “Defender of Orthodoxy.” Probably due to his Alexandrian background, Athanasius was deeply influenced by Origen, whom he titled “the Hardworking” and even “miraculous” (thaumastos; Socrates, EH VI.13). Athanasius composed a letter defending Dionysius of Alexandria, an Origenian, against charges of ‘heresy’ (De Sententia Dionysii); he wrote a biography in praise of Anthony “the Great,” another Origenian (Vita Antonii); and he appointed the Origenian universalist Didymus the Blind (see below) to the head of the Alexandrian catechetical school.

    At the beginning of his De Incarnatione (ca. AD 330), Athanasius argues that since the good God created the world from nothing, evil is therefore ontologically nothing, and those who fully integrate themselves around evil would pass into non-being (3–4). This sets up the reason for the incarnation: God could not allow any of his rational creatures to fall into non-being; it would not be “worthy of God’s goodness” (6.4–10). The same argument was presented by Origen (see my post on his views), for whom only universal restoration is “worthy of the goodness of the God of the universe” (Comm in John VI.296). Athanasius speaks frequently in De Incarn., his Orationes contra Arianos, and his festal letters (see esp. letter 10.4.8–9) about the salvation and restoration of all people due to the incarnation and Christ’s death. This could be understood as referring merely to unlimited atonement, but in light of the Origenian flavor of his argument, should probably be understood as actual universalism.

    Athanasius interprets the aeonian fire as corrective in his exposition of the Psalms. God sends the nations into the aeonian fire and tells them to perish, “so that they may revive and correct themselves” (Exp in Ps IX.16). He knows that aiōn and aiōnios don’t refer strictly to eternity, but rather to the aeons, since in the same passage he glosses eis ton aiōna as “in the next aeon” (neō aiōni). Across his works, Athanasius frequently uses the Greek term that means strictly “eternal” (aidios), but never applies it to punishment. [6] In his commentary on Luke 10:22, he says that those who blaspheme Father, Son, or Holy Spirit will be “liable to the severest chastisement,” punished in this aeon and the next one, but God is still able to bring them to repent (6). The purpose of the fire that Christ sends is “that evil be entirely consumed in all people, and the soul... purified” (festal letter 3.4.8). It’s in this sense that we should interpret his references to aeonian fire in De Incarn. and elsewhere, so he was most likely a universalist.

Didymus the Blind

    Didymus “the Blind,” also known as Didymus “the Seer,” was appointed by Athanasius to the head of the Alexandrian catechetical school in the mid-fourth century and remained there until his death in 398. According to his student Jerome, he referred to Origen as “the second teacher of the church after the apostles.” Unfortunately, when Origen was condemned in the sixth century as a result of the ‘Origenist’ controversy, Didymus’ works were also condemned, so we have only fragments of his exegetical writings. From what we do have, it’s clear that he was a universalist. [7]

    Didymus, in his comments on 1 Cor 15:24–28, holds to the same interpretation as Origen: “death is destroyed in that every soul now subject to death, which is joined to evil, will be joined to Christ” (Comm in 1 Cor 7–8). Also in his comments on John 17:1–2, he emphasizes that the Father gives all beings to Christ, “that no being handed to him may perish”; they will all be saved, and there will no longer be sin nor any need for punishment. This is because the purpose of punishment is not retribution, but correction, to consume “not creatures, but certain conditions and habits” (Comm in Ps 20–21 XXI.15). Indeed, even the devil is not evil by nature, but by his habits, and even physical death was instituted as a restorative punishment (Comm in Gen IIB.109–116).

    Like the other Greek fathers of his day, Didymus is well aware that aiōnios does not mean strictly “eternal.” It can mean “beginningless and endless” when applied to God, but it can also mean simply “imperishable” (and not beginningless), and it can also mean “the time that extends over the life of a human being” (Comm in Job LXXVI.11ff). The ultimate condition of humanity will not be merely aeonian, but “salvation that is beyond the aeons [hyperaiōnios]” (Comm in Zach II.370). Thus, for Didymus, the Scriptural affirmation of aeonian punishment presents no challenge to the eventual restoration of all beings. Indeed, in Rufinus’ and Jerome’s later dispute over Origen, they agree that their teacher “Didymus the seeing prophet” was a universalist who believed even in the restoration of the rational being who became the devil (Rufinus, Apology Against Jerome I.43).

Macarius of Magnesia

    Macarius of Magnesia was a lesser-known Christian apologist of the mid-fourth century, whose only known work is the Apocriticus, a fictional debate between a pagan philosopher and a Christian. In the surviving portions of this work, he says that the end of this aeon will bring punishment for some (IV.13), but ultimately “all creatures will have a second and better beginning” (IV.16). We can be certain Macarius was a universalist, because the ninth-century Nikephoros of Constantinople complained that at the (now-lost) end of the fourth book of the Apocriticus, he taught “the crippled doctrines of the impious and apopleptic Origen... that the chastisement threatened and prepared by God for impious people in the time to come will come to an end” (Epikrisis 12).

Hilary of Poitiers

    Hilary was the bishop of Poitiers in the mid-fourth century, later titled “Hammer of the Arians” and “Athanasius of the West” for his staunch opposition to ‘Arianism.’ He was also one of the first Western fathers (with the possible exception of Novatian) to be influenced by Origen. According to Jerome, Hilary translated over 40,000 lines of Origen’s writings into Latin (Apology Against Rufinus I.2). His own commentaries on Job and the Psalms were heavily influenced by Origen’s commentaries (Jerome, De Viris Illustribus 100). He inherited some of Origen’s interpretations related to universalism, although he was not himself a universalist.

    For example, Hilary believed that Christ’s body incorporates the whole of humanity; this view is found all throughout his writings and is central to his soteriology. [8] He also held that God, strictly speaking, does not get angry or punish directly, but sin brings its own punishment. Thus the purpose of punishment is not retribution but repentance (Tract sup Ps II.16–22). In his commentary on Matthew, he offers the interpretation of the parable of lost sheep that the 100 sheep are the rational beings, and the lost sheep is human nature which will be restored (Comm in Matt XVIII.6). The same interpretation was proposed by Origen and Methodius of Olympus. Finally, Hilary also believed that the “subjection” in 1 Cor 15:24–28 is salvific, and used this to counter the ‘Arian’ interpretation of the Son’s subjection to God (De Trin XI.21–49).

    In spite of all this, Hilary was an infernalist and not a universalist. Although Christ’s body incorporates all humans, people can cut themselves off from this unity through their unbelief. [9] Hilary speaks of “eternal” (aeternum) punishment throughout his tractates on the Psalms, and doesn’t seem to consider that this is translated from aiōnios which doesn’t mean strictly “eternal.” In his comments on 1 Cor 15:24–28, he states that the telos will bring an irrevocable state of punishment for the wicked (De Trin XI.27–29). The “enemies” who are subjected will be saved, but these refer only to the unbelieving Jews, of whom Paul says, “they are enemies for your sakes, but... beloved for the fathers’ sake” (Rom 11:28); therefore, “because they are beloved for the fathers’ sake, they are reserved for the subjection [and not the destruction]” (De Trin XI.32–34). However, Hilary of Poitiers’ attempted synthesis of Western infernalism with Eastern, Origenian universalism doesn’t appear to have spread beyond him.

Marius Victorinus

    Marius Victorinus was a prominent Roman Neoplatonist philosopher who converted to Christianity in the mid-fourth century, and thereafter became a staunch anti-‘Arian.’ The story of his conversion had a deep impact on the young Augustine (Confessions VIII.2.3–5). In his commentaries on Paul’s epistles, Victorinus frequently emphasizes the centrality of faith for salvation in Christ. In his comments on Phil 2:10, he says that every human will eventually confess Christ, and not only every human but every being in the universe; death has already been conquered for “those who believe in him,” and if all beings will confess Christ, death will be conquered for “all of these” (Comm in Phil 2.10 [1211A–B]). In his comments on Eph 1:10, he states,

For not all things which exist – and they include both these very things in the heavens and those above the earth – are restored in Christ; rather, those things which are in Christ [are restored], for there also exist other and alien things. Therefore whatever things are in Christ, these are restored and rise again, whether in the heavens or on the earth. [1245B–C]

At first glance, this may seem to be a denial of universal salvation, but in his Adversus Arium, he is quite clear that every being is in fact “in Christ,” because nothing could possibly exist outside of him who is “the subsistence of all existents” (Adv Ar I.36). Victorinus takes over the Origenian view that the “body of Christ,” the church, is in fact “all souls” (Comm in Eph 1.22–23 [1252A–D]), though this body is now divided and not all believe. The “other and alien things” which will not be restored in Christ must be evilness itself, which per Neoplatonist (and Christian) philosophy is really nothing at all.

    It is because of this that we can be certain that all will be “spiritualized” by Christ in the end, that is, “God will be ‘all in all,’ not only in each one, but in all, therefore all will be God [or ‘divine’], because all will be full of God” (Adv Ar I.39). Christ descended to the lower parts and ascended to heaven in order to perfect every being that could be saved, both human and angelic (Comm in Eph 4.10 [1274A–D]). Just like Origen, Victorinus holds that it is precisely the love of Christ that ensures a soul’s eternal stability in salvation (Comm in Eph 3.18 [1269B–C]). He may have gotten these ideas from Origen’s own writings, since he was proficient in Greek, or from the Eastern church where universalism was then prevalent. Either way, Marius Victorinus is an important Western voice in favor of a Christ-centric and faith-centric universal salvation in this period.

Aphrahat the Persian

    Aphrahat was a Syriac church father, possibly a bishop, who wrote in the mid-fourth century. His surviving works are called the Demonstrations, of which there are twenty-three. In book 8, he expounds his belief that those who die become “nothing” (VIII.2), and that their souls sleep until the resurrection when they are judged (VIII.17–22); the spirit of the righteous that returns to God when they die is precisely the Holy Spirit (VIII.23). Aphrahat refers to this doctrine of soul sleep as “our faith” (VIII.20) and even “the thinking of the whole church” (XXII.26), which provides an interesting window into the thanatology of the early Syriac church.

    In Aphrahat’s view, the sleep of the wicked will be restless, since they dream of their coming judgment (VIII.19). Repentance is impossible after this life; in the next world there will be justice without grace (VII.25–27; VIII.20), contrary to the Origenian view that God’s goodness and justice are the same. The very wicked will not even be judged, but will return to Sheol (sleep? non-existence?) as soon as they are resurrected (XXII.17). The rest of humanity will be judged and will receive varying degrees of either reward and honor or punishment and torment (XXII.18–22). Based on this, Aphrahat can be safely categorized as an infernalist, although a conditionalist with regard to the very wicked.

Ephrem the Syrian

    Ephrem was a Syriac church father who lived in Mesopotamia and eventually settled in Edessa, where he defended the pro-Nicene position against ‘Arians’ and ‘gnostic’ groups. Like Aphrahat, he believed that the state of the dead in Sheol is one of sleep (Carm Nis XLIII.14–16; Hymn de Par VII.2), since the body is necessary for the human being to have full existence (Hymn de Par VIII.4–7). Thanks to Christ’s death and resurrection, every human will be restored to life at the universal resurrection. [10] At that time, there will be “two ways” – each human will either go to Gehenna or Eden (e.g., Carm Nis LXXIII.4).

    There will be varying degrees of punishment for those in Gehenna, in accordance with their sins (Ep ad Publ 2–4). Those in Eden will no longer love or pity those in Gehenna, due to the Abyss in between which severs the love even of family members, but will marvel at the “extent these people have cut off all hope by committing such iniquity” (Hymn de Par I.12–14); indeed, “their punishment does not come to an end” (II.4). There will be resurrection from the first death in Sheol, but there is no escape from the second death in Gehenna (Carm Nis XLIII.15).

    On the other hand, Ephrem considers that “perhaps, for the wicked,” the punishment of Gehenna symbolizes the sinner’s conscience which is tormented by his own sins, and this for the purpose of “repentance of their soul” (Ep ad Publ 22). He believed that physical death was instituted as a restorative punishment to prevent eternal sin, “lest by eating of [the Tree of Life] and living forever, they would have to remain in a life of pain for eternity” (Comm in Gen II.35). He considers, with an attitude of humility and uncertainty, that God’s mercy and forgiveness extends even to those in Gehenna:

Blessed the sinner who has received mercy there [in Gehenna] and is deemed worthy to be given access to the environs of Paradise; even though he remains outside, he may pasture there through grace. As I reflected I was fearful again because I had presumed to suppose that there might be between the Garden and the Fire a place where those who have found mercy can receive chastisement and forgiveness.

Praise to the Just One who rules with his grace; he is the Good One who never draws in the limits of his goodness; even to the wicked he stretches forth in his compassion. His divine cloud hovers over all that is his; it drips dew even on that fire of punishment so that, of his mercy, it enables even the embittered to taste of the drops of its refreshment. (Hymn de Par X.14–15)

In his commentary on the gospels, he refers to the ‘unforgivable sin’ of blasphemy of the Spirit (Matt 12:32), and says that

God will require the retribution of the most serious sin in Gehenna... But not even this sin will prevent that a person may be justified eventually. When one will have made retribution in Gehenna, [God] will reward him for this in the Kingdom. (Comm in Diat X.4)

In one of his homilies on Christ’s descent to Sheol, he represents Death as saying to Satan, “perhaps due to mercy, Gehenna will be emptied, and you will remain there alone with your ministers” (Carm Nis LIX.8). Thus, it appears that Ephrem was a tentative or hopeful universalist, who believed (in spite of his more fearful statements elsewhere) that God might allow repentance in Gehenna, and eventually save all human beings in this way. [11]

Conclusion

    The first half of the fourth century saw universalism’s popularity increase further across the church. The leaders of the three main (non-‘Arian’) Nicene factions – the Eusebian ‘subordinationists,’ the Marcellian modalists, and the Athanasian trinitarians – all were universalists, believing in the eventual salvation of at least all humanity. Didymus the Blind held even to the ultimate salvation of the rational creature who became the devil. In the West, Hilary of Poitiers remained an infernalist, but incorporated aspects of Origenian universalism into his eschatology, including the restorative nature of punishment and the salvific nature of “subjection.” Marius Victorinus, another Western anti-‘Arian,’ was certainly a universalist. In the Syriac church, Aphrahat was both an infernalist and a conditionalist (with regard to the very wicked), and Ephrem was a tentative or hopeful universalist.

Part 7: Fourth-Century Fathers (2/2)

______________________________

[1] See his letter to his church following the council.

[2] On the question of Eusebius’ subordinationism or anti-subordinationism, see Christopher Beeley, “Eusebius’ Contra Marcellum. Anti-Modalist Doctrine and Orthodox Christology,” Zeitschrift für Antikes Christentum 12 (2008): 433–52; Ilaria Ramelli, “Origen’s Anti-Subordinationism and its Heritage in the Nicene and Cappadocian Line,” Vigilae Christianae 65 (2011): 38–49.

[3] Ilaria Ramelli and David Konstan, Terms for Eternity (Piscataway, NJ: Gorgias Press, 2013), 142–57.

[4] R. P. C. Hanson, The Search for the Christian Doctrine of God (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2005); which provides a detailed history of the fourth-century theological conflicts and Marcellus’ role in them.

[5] Joseph T. Lienhard, “The Exegesis of 1 Cor 15, 24-28 from Marcellus of Ancyra to Theodoret of Cyrus,” Vigilae Christianae 37 (1983): 341–47. Despite Lienhard’s argument, the attribution of De Incarnatione to Marcellus seems very plausible to me, given its clearly modalistic reading of certain passages and its affirmation that God will rule through the Logos after ruling through the human Christ. This unique combination of views strongly suggests a Marcellian origin.

[6] Ramelli and Konstan, Terms for Eternity, 157–72.

[7] Since there are no easily accessible English translations of Didymus’ writings, I’m relying on Ramelli’s translation in The Christian Doctrine of Apokatastasis for this section.

[8] Ellen Scully, Physicalist Soteriology in Hilary of Poitiers (Leiden: Brill, 2015).

[9] Scully, Physicalist Soteriology, 147–54.

[10] Thomas Buchan, “Blessed is He who has brought Adam from Sheol”: Christ’s Descent to the Dead in the Theology of Saint Ephrem the Syrian (Piscataway, NJ: Gorgias Press, 2014), 293–310.

[11] Buchan, “Blessed is He who has brought Adam from Sheol”, 318–27; Kees den Biesen, “The Irresistible Love of God. Two Syrian Church Fathers on Universal Salvation in Christ,” in Between the Cross and the Crescent (Rome: Pontifical Oriental Institute, 2018), 438–43.

The case for Aristotelian metaphysics (part 2 of 2)

Part 1 Substance and accident     As we’ve seen, in any instance of change, there must be both something that changes and something that und...