Resurrection and metaphysical anthropology (part 2 of 2)

Part 1: substance dualism and physicalism

Hylomorphic dualism

    Hylomorphic dualism is a middle ground view between substance dualism and physicalism. This view is based in hylomorphism, the Aristotelian doctrine that corporeal substances are made up of matter (hylē) and form (morphē). Form is that which gives a substance its attributes (e.g., color, shape, size) and powers, while matter is what receives and individuates form. (Forms, such as dog-ness and triangularity, don’t exist by themselves – at least, not usually – they exist in individual substances, like dogs and triangles, which are distinguished by their unique parcels of matter.)

    Hylomorphism was first proposed to help explain change. For change to really happen, there must be something that underlies and stays the same, and something that changes. If the former doesn’t exist, then nothing really changes, things just come into and go out of existence. (For example: if nothing underlies and persists through change, then a banana doesn’t change from green to yellow, instead a green banana goes out of existence and a yellow banana comes into existence.) If the latter doesn’t exist, then nothing ever changes at all.

    When it comes to substantial change (change from one substance to another), the thing that underlies must be something that is not itself a substance, but can take on new attributes and powers (this is what Aristotle called “matter”), and there must be something in virtue of which the matter comes to have new attributes and powers (this is what Aristotle called “form”). Even hyper-reductionist physicalists should agree that substantial change occurs, since fundamental particles can decay into other kinds of fundamental particles. Thus, the existence of matter and form as metaphysical parts of substances is well-grounded in the fact that change (especially substantial change) really happens.

    Hylomorphic dualism is just the application of hylomorphism to human persons. Like all other material substances, humans have both matter – which individuates us from other humans – and substantial form – which gives us the attributes and powers that are proper to humans. This includes not just attributes like shape and size, but also our perceptual and cognitive powers. Aristotle referred to the form of a living thing as its “soul” (psychē); not just for humans, but for other vegetative and sentient life as well. However, he argued that the human form/soul is unique because it has a rational intellect which is immaterial and naturally indestructible (De Anima 3.4-7).

    This view avoids the problems that are associated with substance dualism and physicalism. Unlike substance dualism, hylomorphic dualism conceives of a human as a single substance comprising both body and mind. There is therefore no interaction problem, because the form of a person ‘interacts’ with her matter in the same way that form and matter ‘interact’ in any other material substance, namely, by informing its attributes and powers (both bodily and mental). There is also no problem of personal identity, because a person is an ontological whole rather than a mere aggregate of two distinct substances (her body and her mind). Likewise, the fact that our perception and cognition are fundamentally embodied poses no issue for hylomorphic dualism, because a person’s mind is integrated with her body as proper parts of one and the same substance.

    Hylomorphic dualism can also sidestep the arguments against physicalism that I gave earlier. These arguments show that our cognitive processes can’t be wholly corporeal, since our concepts are inherently determinate and universal, whereas physical facts are indeterminate and particular. This also shows that our intellect isn’t wholly material in the Aristotelian sense, because our concepts can abstract away matter to get at the universal forms like triangularity. Hylomorphic dualists aren’t committed to saying that humans are wholly material; we can say, as Aristotle did, that the human form/soul has some operations that are immaterial.

    By the scholastic principle agere sequitur esse (“action follows being”), the fact that the human substantial form has immaterial operations means that it also has an immaterial mode of subsistence. Since my intellect isn’t tied to or reducible to my body, unlike my other operations – for example, sight, which is tied to (at least) my eyes and the occipital lobe of my brain – it can exist even if my body does not. Indeed, as an immaterial thing, it’s not naturally destructible as material substances are. When I die, and my matter ceases to be informed by my substantial form, the immaterial operations of my substantial form that don’t inform any matter will continue to exist, and so my substantial form will still exist. And it will exist in an individualized way, distinguished from other human substantial forms by its unique causal history (having been combined with my matter).

    However, my form will be an incomplete substance after my death. It won’t be me, because I am a composite substance made up of both matter and form. It won’t naturally undergo new perceptual experiences, because my perceptual abilities are tied to my body (see the arguments against substance dualism), and it won’t be able to form any new concepts, because new concepts are formed based on our experiences of the external world (even though concepts aren’t reducible to perception). And although this is controversial among hylomorphic dualists, I don’t think the post-mortem human form is naturally conscious, at least not apart from supernatural intervention. If syncope (temporary blood loss to the brain) results in a loss of consciousness, then the complete disconnection from the brain that comes with death should also result in a loss of consciousness, even though the human form persists through both these things.

    In summary, based purely on philosophical considerations in the philosophy of mind, we can know that humans exist as a composite of body and form/soul, that the form/soul is partially immaterial, and that our form/soul persists after our death in an individuated but severely impaired way. How does this square with Scripture and our three axioms about the afterlife?

Hylomorphic dualism and Christian anthropology

    According to Genesis 2:7, when God created the human, he first made a body out of dust and then breathed spirit/breath (Heb: ruach; Gk: pneuma) into it, and “the human became a living soul.” The body apart from the spirit is dead (Jas. 2:26), and at death, the body/dust returns to the earth and the spirit/breath returns to God (Ps. 104:29; 146:4; Ecc. 12:7; cf. Zech. 12:1; Acts 7:59). It appears that a person’s spirit continues to be individualized after her death, as evidenced by the little girl whose “spirit returned” when Jesus resurrected her (Lk. 8:54-55), and by the examples of Jesus (who gave up “his spirit”; Matt. 27:50; Lk. 23:46; John 19:30) and Stephen (who told Jesus to “receive my spirit”; Acts 7:59). A soul, on the other hand, can be killed (e.g., Num. 31:19; 35:11, 15, 30; Josh. 20:3, 9; Matt. 10:28; Mk. 3:4) and be dead (e.g., Lev. 21:11; Num. 6:6; 19:11, 13; Josh. 2:13; Jas. 5:20; Rev. 16:3).

    These are the clearest passages that deal with the relationship between body, spirit, and soul. Based on this, it seems that the Aristotelian concept of the human ‘soul’ or substantial form actually corresponds to the Scriptural concept of spirit, as the principle that animates a person and continues to exist after a person’s death. The Scriptural concept of soul corresponds not to a person’s substantial form, but to the person herself, who is a composite of body and spirit and can die. Neither substance dualism nor physicalism correspond as well as hylomorphic dualism to the Scriptural data, since the Aristotelian categories of matter, form, and substance map almost one-to-one onto the Scriptural categories of body, spirit, and soul.

The centrality of bodily resurrection

    But what about the three claims that nearly all Christians affirm about the afterlife? The first claim is that the bodily resurrection is our primary hope for life after death. This is well-grounded in Paul’s argument for the resurrection, in which he says that if there is no resurrection, “those who have died in Christ have perished... we are of all people most to be pitied” (1 Cor. 15:12-19). Paul says that the resurrection is the hope for those who grieve (1 Thess. 4:13-18), and that he doesn’t want to be “unclothed,” that is, bodiless (2 Cor. 5:3-4). In the New Testament, the resurrection is mentioned far more than any conscious intermediate state, if such a state is mentioned at all (the most likely prooftext for such a state is Luke 16:19-31, which is plausibly a parable).

    Hylomorphic dualism provides a strong philosophical basis for this belief. My substantial form will continue to exist immaterially beyond my death, but in a severely impaired way, without new perceptual experiences and plausibly without any consciousness at all. This fact is reflected in the Hebrew Bible’s assertions that the dead cannot know or praise God (Ps. 6:4-5; 30:8-10; 88:9-12; 115:17; Isa. 38:17-19), and that their perception and cognition are at least severely impaired (Ps. 146:3-4; Ecc. 9:5-10). It’s also reflected in the metaphor of death as sleep, which is found all throughout the Scriptures. Sleep is an accurate metaphor for death in another way: if my form does undergo conscious experiences after death, they won’t be directly experienced by me, but I will remember them when I’m resurrected, like my memories of a dream when I wake up from sleep.

    The only way for me to exist normally after death, and indeed for me to exist at all after death (since I am a composite of matter and form), is for my form to once again inform matter and become part of a material substance. This is just metaphysical language for bodily resurrection. Therefore, unlike substance dualism and physicalism, hylomorphic dualism provides both a motive and a mechanism for resurrection.

The immediacy of paradise

    The second claim that nearly all Christians affirm about the afterlife is that some people will have immediate, paradisiacal existence after death. Can hylomorphic dualism explain this? Yes, and it follows the Non-Existence Thesis rather than the Intermediate State Thesis (see above). A person, who is the composite of her matter and form, doesn’t exist after her death. Her first conscious experience after death will be at the resurrection. Even if we assume (as I don’t) that her spirit has conscious experiences between death and resurrection, she won’t experience them, she’ll just remember them when she’s resurrected, analogously to how we can recall dreams after we wake from sleep. Therefore, from her perspective, she will immediately experience paradise after she dies.

The identity of the dead and resurrected person

    The third claim, that the person who dies is numerically identical to the person who is resurrected, might be the hardest one to explain on a hylomorphic view. Since I affirm that the person (a composite of matter and form) ceases to exist between death and the resurrection, I also have to deny the widely accepted axiom No Gappy Existence: that one and the same thing can’t begin to exist more than once. 

    However, unlike physicalist Christians, hylomorphic dualists can deny NGE without any weird consequences about personal identity. Whereas physicalists say that a person just is identical to a certain physical process, hylomorphists say that a person is constituted by matter that’s informed by a particular substantial form. If a person ceases to exist, but her individual substantial form continues to exist, then that same person can come into existence again if her form once again begins to inform matter. Since the person isn’t annihilated, but corrupted (broken up) into matter and form, her particular form and matter can recombine to generate the same person. There’s no danger that two copies of the same person could exist if her body is duplicated, as in physicalism. That’s not even a metaphysical possibility, because a person is a single material substance with a particular substantial form.

    In fact, hylomorphists already have good reason to deny NGE, even apart from any considerations about bodily resurrection (Toner 2015). When two or more substances combine to form one substance (for example, hydrogen and oxygen making water), the initial substances cease to exist actually, but exist virtually or potentially in the new substance, and can begin to exist actually again (so the same hydrogen and oxygen atoms can be recovered from an H2O molecule). Aristotle argues for this when he responds to a metaphysical argument against the possibility of combination:

For, according to some thinkers, it is impossible for one thing to be combined with another. They argue that (i) if both the ‘combined’ constituents persist unaltered, they are no more ‘combined’ now than they were before, but are in the same condition: while (ii) if one has been destroyed, the constituents have not been ‘combined’ – on the contrary, one constituent is and the other is not, whereas ‘combination’ demands uniformity of condition in them both: and on the same principle (iii) even if both the combining constituents have been destroyed as a result of their coalescence, they cannot ‘have been combined’ since they have no being at all. (De Gen. et Cor. 1.10)

This Parmenidean argument seeks to show that combination is impossible. You can’t really combine two things to get a third thing, because you’re either left with (1) the mere aggregate of two things, (2) one of the initial two things, or (3) the initial two things are annihilated and a third thing is created. Like Parmenides’ argument against the possibility of change, this argument relies on a stark distinction between existence and non-existence. You can’t have two things and a third thing that exist in the same way, at the same place, at the same time, so combination is impossible.

    Aristotle rebuts this conclusion by saying that there’s something in between actual existence and non-existence, namely potential existence. When two substances are combined, they exist potentially in the new substance, which exists actually. But this means that NGE is wrong, because things can cease to exist actually and begin to exist actually again, as long as they have potential existence in between. Since I do exist potentially after my death, inasmuch as my individual form still exists and has the potential to combine with matter, hylomorphism can account for my personal identity at the resurrection.

Conclusion

    The three claims of Christianity about the afterlife appear inconsistent, since the central importance of bodily resurrection seems to conflict with the immediacy of paradise after death. But from considerations in the philosophy of mind, independent of theological concerns about resurrection, we can determine that hylomorphic dualism is true, which makes bodily resurrection not only logically possible but plausible. There's a solid metaphysical basis to accept the Scriptural tripartite division of humans into body (matter), spirit (form), and soul (substance), as well as the survival of the spirit after death and the possibility of bodily resurrection. Our Christian hope for the afterlife is philosophically sound!

Appendix: survivalism vs. corruptionism

    There’s a debate among hylomorphic dualists about whether a human person survives between death and resurrection (survivalism), or the human form between death and resurrection does not constitute a human person (corruptionism). I think corruptionism is pretty obviously true from a hylomorphist perspective, so I didn’t really discuss the debate above. Here, though, I’ll briefly explain why I think corruptionism is correct.

    First, there’s an exegetical debate about whether Thomas Aquinas was a survivalist or a corruptionist. Since I don’t feel the need to agree with Aquinas on everything, I don’t think this has much bearing on whether or not corruptionism is true. But it’s worth noting that Aquinas was pretty clearly a corruptionist and not a survivalist. Early in his career, he talked explicitly about this topic, in his Commentary on the Sentences. Here, he rejected Plato’s substance dualism in favor of Aristotle’s hylomorphic dualism:

...the opinion of Aristotle, which all current [authors] follow, [is] that the soul is united to the body as form to matter. Hence the soul is a part of human nature, and not some nature per se. And since the notion of a part is contrary to the notion of a person, as was said, therefore the separated soul cannot be called a person, since even though it is not actually a part [when] separated, nevertheless it has the nature to be a part. (In Sent. III.5.3.2; transl. Nevitt 2016)

Likewise, in his commentary on Paul’s (1 Cor. 15) and Jesus’ (Mk. 12:24-27) arguments for the bodily resurrection, Aquinas insisted that these arguments depend on the separated spirit not being a person:

The soul of Abraham is not, strictly speaking, Abraham himself, but it is a part of him. The same goes for the others [i.e. Isaac and Jacob]. Hence the life of the soul of Abraham would not be sufficient for Abraham to be living, nor for the God of Abraham to be the God of the living; but [this] requires the life of the whole composite, namely of soul and body. (In Sent. IV.43.1.1; transl. Nevitt 2016)

Man naturally desires his own salvation. But the soul, since it is a part of the man, is not the whole man; and I am not my soul. Thus, even though the soul attains salvation in the afterlife, nevertheless I – or any man – do not. (Super 1 Cor. 15.2.924; transl. Reese 2024)

Aquinas also said in various places, up through his last writings, that Christ didn’t exist as a human person while he was dead, which implies that the separated human form by itself isn’t a person (Nevitt 2016). The standard survivalist response is that although the human form isn’t a person by itself, it does somehow constitute a person; but this would go against Aquinas’ insistence that we don’t attain salvation if our separated form does.

    The metaphysical argument for corruptionism is also quite straightforward. The essence of a human, which is rational animality, includes both material (animality) and immaterial (rationality) aspects. If it only included immaterial aspects, then hylomorphic dualism would be no different than substance dualism, since our connection to our bodies would be only accidental. But nothing can exist without all the things that are essential to it; that’s what it means for something to be essential. Therefore, no human being can exist without both matter and form, and a person ceases to exist when her matter and form separate (Nevitt 2020). Yes, her form continues to subsist immaterially, but as its own incomplete, non-human substance, not as her.

    Finally, on the theological side of the debate, survivalists consistently claim to have the upper hand. This is because most hylomorphic dualists are Catholics, who accept the doctrines of purgatory before resurrection and praying to the saints, which seem to require that people exist between death and the resurrection. I’m not a Catholic, so I don’t particularly care whether corruptionism is compatible with praying to the saints – although it’s worth noting that Aquinas believed it is (In Sent. III.22.1.1; ST II-II.83.11). In fact, I’m inclined to believe our separated spirits aren’t conscious at all, in light of various Scriptural passages that indicate that. The numerous places across Scripture where dead people are said to be “no more” also supports corruptionism over survivalism.

    In my estimation, corruptionism has the upper hand over survivalism in terms of metaphysics, theology, and Thomistic exegesis. This means that death really is as serious as it appears (Reese 2024). It’s not just a gateway to heaven, it means that we cease to exist; death truly is the “last enemy” which will eventually be conquered by God (1 Cor. 15:26). Any other view would make bodily resurrection superfluous, since it would make the body merely accidental to human existence. This should make us even more grateful that God has provided a way for death to be defeated, namely resurrection in Christ!

Resurrection and metaphysical anthropology (part 1 of 2)

    Is bodily resurrection something desirable, or even a metaphysical possibility? According to nearly all Christians, it is. But this view has been ridiculed by some non-Christians since the very earliest days of Christianity, so much that the apostle Paul had to defend the doctrine of the resurrection against detractors in his letter to the Corinthian church (1 Cor. 15). While it would be easy for Christians to just ignore these detractors, the fact is that some of their concerns about the resurrection do have philosophical weight. In this post, I'll take a look at the concerns that Christian claims about the afterlife are inconsistent, and that it's impossible for personal identity to continue through the resurrection.

The problem of the resurrection

    There are three claims about the afterlife that are (or should be) affirmed by nearly all Christians, and which have very strong Scriptural support:

1. The bodily resurrection is our primary hope for life after death.

2. Some people have immediate, post-mortem, paradisiacal existence.

3. The person who dies is (numerically) the person who is resurrected.

    The first claim is clearly seen throughout the writings of Paul, who repeatedly emphasizes the importance of resurrection (Rom. 8:9-23; 1 Cor. 15; 2 Cor. 4:17-5:8; 1 Thess. 4:13-18). It’s also found all across the New Testament. For example, Jesus himself emphasized that the bodily resurrection of the Israelite patriarchs is necessary for them to be “living” (Matt. 22:29-32; Mk. 12:24-27; Lk. 20:34-38). Furthermore, if bodily resurrection were merely a superfluous add-on to our post-mortem existence, and not central to life after death, then the bodily resurrection of Christ would also be merely superfluous – but Jesus’ resurrection is central to the Christian faith, so our resurrection is central to our hope. (This is Paul’s argument in 1 Corinthians 15:1-19.)

    The second claim also finds much Scriptural support. To the rebel who was crucified beside him, Jesus said, “Truly I tell you, today you will be with me in paradise” (Lk. 23:43). (Admittedly, if this sentence were punctuated differently – which is a subjective translation decision – it would have a different meaning.) Paul told one of his congregations that his death, for him, would be “gain” because he would “depart and be with Christ” (Phil. 1:21-23). Christians may reasonably disagree on who exactly will immediately enter a paradisiacal existence after death, whether this is true of just martyrs, or of all Christians, or even (in the extreme case of Hosea Ballou) all people. But I’m unaware of any Christian group that denies that anyone will immediately enter paradise after death.

    The third claim follows from the first claim. If the person who is resurrected isn’t the same as the person who died, then the resurrection isn’t really our hope, but the hope of someone else who doesn’t exist yet. Even if someone with my exact memories is created at the resurrection, that means nothing to me if that person isn’t numerically identical to me.

    However, these three claims might be inconsistent. Let’s see why. Claim 2 could be interpreted in two ways:

Intermediate State Thesis (IST): at least some people exist in a disembodied, paradisiacal state between death and the resurrection.

Non-Existence Thesis (NET): at least some people don’t exist between death and resurrection, so that this interval is immediate for them.

IST has been the most common view throughout Christian history, but it undercuts claim 1: if our disembodied state is paradisiacal, then bodily resurrection appears superfluous. This tension was recognized by at least some early church writers, including Irenaeus and Augustine (Turner 2015, 37-46), and it was also recognized by Aquinas, who denied IST for this reason (In Sent. IV.43.1.1; Super 1 Cor. 15.2.924). On the other hand, NET undercuts claim 3 due to a widely accepted philosophical axiom that we’ll call No Gappy Existence (NGE): it isn’t possible for one and the same thing to come into existence more than once. If a fire is started, stopped, and then started again, the second fire isn’t numerically identical to the first. It’s also impossible for a person to cease to exist altogether and then come into existence as the same person.

    Therefore, the bodily resurrection poses a philosophical problem for Christians. It’s difficult to hold IST and claim 1 (the centrality of bodily resurrection) at the same time. But it’s also difficult to hold NET and claim 3 (the numerical identity of the dead and resurrected person) at the same time, given the widely accepted axiom NGE. How, then, can we interpret claims 1-3 to be self-consistent?

Substance dualism

    In modern metaphysical anthropology, views about human persons are divided between dualism and physicalism. Dualism says that people are (in some sense) partially corporeal and partially incorporeal, whereas physicalism says that people are entirely corporeal and physical. The most common dualist view is called substance dualism: this is the view that the mind and body are two substances, an incorporeal one and a corporeal one. A substance is an object with independent ontological reality, so that properties (like color, shape, and size) inhere in substances, but substances don’t inhere in anything else. Substance dualism can be interpreted in two ways: either a person simply is her mind, or she is the composite of her mind and body.

Substance dualism and the resurrection

    Let’s take the first interpretation. If a person is her mind, then it’s obvious how claim 2 (immediate paradisiacal existence) could be true, since she (i.e., her mind) can exist independently of a body after death. But this makes claim 2 even harder to reconcile with claim 1 (the centrality of bodily resurrection), since the body is totally superfluous to the flourishing existence of any person. In fact, two of the most historically prominent substance dualists, Plato and Descartes, both saw the body as a sort of prison for the mind/person. This view is completely foreign to the New Testament, as N. T. Wright argues strongly in his book The Resurrection of the Son of God, and it’s contrary to claim 1.

    What about the second interpretation? If a person is the composite of her mind and body, then claim 2 could still be true in virtue of an incorporeal part of her (i.e., her mind) that survives after death. It might also be easier to reconcile with claim 1: bodily resurrection is important because the body is a proper part of a person. But this view seems to run into insuperable difficulties about personal identity, because it means that the person isn’t a thinker or a knower, her mind is. Nor does the person do anything corporeal, her body does. Since she isn’t a substance, but merely the aggregate of two substances (mind and body), the person doesn’t actually do anything. It follows that persons, like other mere aggregates of substances (such as a table with a banana on it), are merely mental constructs. I don’t think it’s even possible to coherently accept this view, since someone who accepts it is denying that they exist. This is also contrary to claim 3 (the numerical identity of the dead and resurrected person), since that claim relies on a concept of real personal identity.

    Finally, the view of the intermediate state that substance dualism implies isn’t Scriptural. Paul looked forward to the resurrection body, but didn’t want to be “unclothed,” that is, without a body (2 Cor. 5:3-4). The Hebrew Bible consistently describes those who are dead as being “no more” (Gen. 37:30; 42:13, 36; Job 27:19; Ps. 37:10, 36; 39:13; 104:35; Isa. 17:14; Jer. 31:15; Lam. 5:7; Ezek. 26:21; 27:36; 28:19; cf. Matt. 2:18), and its wisdom literature repeatedly insists that the dead cannot praise or know God (Ps. 6:4-5; 30:8-10; 88:9-12; 115:17; Isa. 38:17-19), and that their perceptual and cognitive abilities are at the very least severely impaired (Ps. 146:3-4; Ecc. 9:5-10). Both the Hebrew Bible and New Testament writers use sleep as a metaphor for death, which suggests that death impairs a person’s knowledge of the external world and her cognitive abilities. All this is contrary to substance dualism, which entails that embodiment is irrelevant to mental activity.

Substance dualism and philosophy of mind

    In addition to the theological problems with substance dualism (it seems to contradict claims 1 and/or 3), there are a number of philosophical problems. The interaction problem argues that it’s impossible for a corporeal substance (the body) and an incorporeal substance (the mind) to interact with each other. Christians have good reason to accept that incorporeal substances can affect corporeal ones, since we already believe that an incorporeal God can affect the corporeal world. But the reverse is harder to affirm. Why is it the case that damage to the brain can damage a person’s perceptive and cognitive abilities, if they are attributes of a distinct substance? Why does stimulating the brain in a particular way have predictable effects on a person’s conscious experience? Why, for that matter, is the incorporeal mind connected to this particular body and not any other corporeal thing?

   This leads to another problem, which is the fundamentally embodied nature of perception and cognition. If our conscious experiences are mere representations of actual things, projected on a Cartesian theater in our minds, then we can never know the corporeal world as it is. My conscious experience could be exactly the same even if the world were completely different, or didn’t exist at all. To avoid radical epistemic skepticism, there can’t be an infinite regress of representations; at some point, there must be direct perception of the external world, which implies that the mind isn’t wholly incorporeal.

    Likewise, cognition is essentially embodied, since our concepts are set in a (largely subconscious) network of assumptions about the external world. To use an example given by Ed Feser (2024, chap. 7), if I go to a restaurant and say, “Bring me a steak,” I’m employing at least the concepts of steak and bringing. But this comes with background assumptions about the external world, like that the waiter is actually predisposed to bring me a steak, that she will do so on a plate, that she will put it on the table and not in my pocket, etc. Furthermore, the use of language presupposes common experience, that our words can really (and not merely seem to) refer to the same things. But if substance dualism is true, then there is no common environment, just the way things seem to each of us. Therefore, since arguments for substance dualism rely on such shared concepts, it’s self-defeating.

Physicalism

     The non-dualist view of human persons is physicalism, which says that people are wholly corporeal with no incorporeal parts or properties. This comes in two flavors: reductive, which says that the mind exists but is reducible to the physical, and eliminativist, which says that mental states really don’t exist at all. I think that eliminativism is self-defeating, because to accept eliminativism requires things like concepts, beliefs, and truth, which the eliminativist denies are real things. (Eliminativist philosopher Patricia Churchland says that we need a “successor concept to truth,” that has not yet been found, which would mean that statements like “eliminativism is true” have no determinable meaning.) Even if this doesn’t mean that eliminativism itself is necessarily false, it does show that no one can coherently accept eliminativism as true.

Physicalism and the resurrection

    Physicalism fails to make claims 1-3 consistent. If a person simply is, or is reducible to, her body, then she ceases to exist when the physical processes that constitute her life stop. But according to the axiom No Gappy Existence, that same person can’t begin to exist again at the resurrection; at best, a precise copy of her will begin to exist, which is contrary to claim 3.

    The proposed solutions to this problem aren’t very convincing. The “simulacrum” model suggests that God transports a person’s body away at the moment of death, replacing it with a simulacrum, and keeping it in stasis until the resurrection. The “falling elevator” model suggests that a person’s body undergoes some kind of metaphysical fission at death, and one part remains on earth while the other is taken by God and kept in stasis until the resurrection. Both of these models are just strange, and rely on controversial metaphysics. The “simulacrum” model implies that God is actively deceiving us about where a person’s body is after death, and the “falling elevator” model has to say that the corpse and the body in stasis are somehow both numerically identical to the dead person’s body.

    On the other hand, a physicalist could deny NGE and say that a person just ceases to exist after death and comes back into existence at the resurrection when God creates an identical body. But this also leads to strange conclusions. If all that is required for personal identity is for there to be an identical body with identical neurological states, then God could theoretically create two or more of the one and the same person by duplicating their body. Therefore, physicalism can only deny NGE at the expense of losing a robust account of numerical personal identity.

Physicalism and philosophy of mind

    There are also philosophical problems with reductive physicalism. For one thing, conceptual thinking is determinate, but physical processes aren’t determinate, which entails that conceptual thinking isn’t wholly reducible to physical processes (Ross 1992Feser 2013). One example is given by Kripke (1982, 7-54). Suppose that you have never added numbers higher than 56, and you’re asked to add 60 + 61. You answer “121,” but a skeptic asks you how you know this. Perhaps what was meant by “+” wasn’t addition, but “quaddition”:

x quus y = x + y if x, y < 57; = 5 otherwise.

The correct answer, therefore, might be 5 and not 121. This seems absurd, but the physical facts don’t militate in favor of one answer over the other; you’ve never added numbers higher than 56, so what you meant in the past by “plus” could have been addition or quaddition. Even if you consciously think, “What I mean by ‘plus’ is addition and not quaddition,” this only pushes the issue a step back. The physical facts about the words “plus” and “addition” and your neurological states when you think those words have no determinate meaning other than what we give them.

    Another example is given by Quine (1960). Suppose you’re a field anthropologist following a native person who points at a rabbit and says, “Gavagai!” You might take “gavagai” to mean “rabbit,” but none of the physical facts about the situation require this; it could also mean “undetached rabbit part” or “landscape that includes at least one rabbit” or any number of other things. Even if you knew every physical fact about the native’s neurological state and the surrounding environment, you wouldn’t be able to tell which of these things he meant by “gavagai.” Surely, though, he did mean something determinate when he said “gavagai.” This implies that his concept “gavagai” isn’t reducible to physical facts.

    The fact is, there can’t be an infinite regress of things that merely have meaning because of other things (which are called instrumental signs). In order for anything to have determinate meaning, the regress must stop at things that not only have meaning but are meaning (formal signs), and are therefore irreducible to physical processes. If we deny that concepts and formal functions (like addition and modus ponens) have no determinate meaning, then we deny that our own arguments are logically valid, which is self-defeating.

    A related argument for the incorporeality of the intellect is that our concepts are abstract universals, but nothing physical is an abstract universal. For example, our concept “triangle” doesn’t correspond to any physical triangle, but to that which is common to all triangles (being a closed polygon with three sides). For a triangle to be physical means that it instantiates a certain way that triangles can be, and not triangularity itself. The fact that we can conceive of universals like triangularity and redness, abstracted from any concrete instantiation of those universals, implies that at least some of our concepts aren’t reducible to physical facts. 

    Furthermore, there are a larger number of possible concepts than possible physical configurations, which also implies that at least some concepts aren’t reducible to physical facts. In fact, there’s a potential infinity of concepts! For example, there is a possible concept for each natural number (which is an infinite set). Josh Rasmussen (2015; w/ Bailey 2020) has advanced a formal mathematical argument, based on Cantor’s Theorem, that the number of possible thoughts must in principle be larger than the number of possible physical configurations.

    In summary, physicalism suffers from quite a few metaphysical problems (and the ones I mentioned here aren’t the only ones). Our conceptual abilities can’t be corporeal because concepts have determinate meaning, whereas physical processes have no inherent meaning, and concepts are abstract universals, whereas physical things are concrete particulars. Furthermore, the number of possible concepts must be larger than the number of possibly physical configurations. These facts show that our conceptual abilities (our rational intellect) must be at least partly incorporeal. (However, our perceptual abilities could be wholly corporeal.)

Next week: A solution to the problem

Resurrection and metaphysical anthropology (part 2 of 2)

Part 1: substance dualism and physicalism Hylomorphic dualism     Hylomorphic dualism is a middle ground view between substance dualism and ...